BOOK REVIEWS
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
Robert Summers. Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory. Ithaca and
London: Cornell University Press, 1982. Pp. 295 [$24.501. Reviewed by David
Stevens.*
Introduction
Robert Summers’ Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory’ is a
difficult and, in many places, ponderous book that attempts to describe,
develop and criticize a theory of law which Summers calls “pragmatic in-
strumentalism”. This theory, he claims, “qualifies as America’s only indig-
enous legal theory and represents a genuine and substantial contribution to
Western legal thought”. 2 Summers states that his primary aim in the book
is to explore “the instrumental and pragmatic facets of legal phenomena”, 3
and not to present an historical study of the various American figures whom
he identifies as the intellectual progenitors of his theory. Among his sec-
ondary aims is the provision of “a comprehensive framework within which
it may be possible to make instrumentalist theorizing … somewhat more
intelligible and coherent than it has been previously.”‘4
Summers’ book is a synthesis and elaboration of three articles that he
has written during the last eight years. Pragmatic Instrumentalism in Twen-
tieth Century American Legal Thought – A Synthesis and Critique of Our
Dominant General Theory about Law and its Use5 is a lengthy but more
succinct statement of the thesis presented in the book under review and
probably all that needed to be said on the subject. Professor Fuller’s Jur-
isprudence and America’s Dominant Philosohpy of Law6 is a short account
of the major points of disagreement between Lon Fuller and the American
Of The Faculty of Law, McGill University.
IRobert Samuel Summers, Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory (1982).
2Ibid., 12. The author qualifies this statement by adding that the theory “is far from a
comprehenslve and finished effort”.
‘Ibid.
4Ibid., 13.
5(1981) 66 Cornell L. Rev. 861.
6(1978) 92 Harv. L. Rev. 433.
McGill Law Journal 1984
Revue de droit de McGill
REVUE DE DROIT DE McGILL
[Vol. 29
legal realists. Naive Instrumentalism and the Law7 is one of a collection of
essays in honour of H.L.A. Hart. In it, Summers criticizes “naive instru-
mentalism” by arguing for many “forms of goal-structures” and conse-
quently many varieties of instrumentalism in the law. In addition, earlier
versions or portions of the book have appeared in Dutch in 1981, and
German in 1982.
Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory joins what has become
an American academic pastime of substantial proportions: the re-appraisal
and occasional rehabilitation of a mildly provocative perspective on law –
legal realism –
and the canonization of the heretofore merely legendary
Oliver Wendell Holmes. 8 It seems that each generation of American lawyers,
beginning fifty years ago when Karl Nickerson Llewellyn vouched that “Holmes’
mind had travelled most of the road [of realistic jurisprudence] two gen-
erations back”, has felt a compelling urge to come to terms with the myth
of Holmes and to measure their jurisprudence against his thought.9 In the
words of one contemporary American intellectual historian, G. Edward White:
71n P. Hacker & J. Raz, eds, Law, Morality, and Society: Essays in Honour of LL.A. Hart
(1977) 119. In an earlier article, The Technique Element in Law (1971) 59 Calif. L. Rev. 733,
Summers developed a taxonomy for the kind of instrumentalist theory he expounds in parts
three and four, of his book, so perhaps it would be more accurate to say that the book under
review is a synthesis of four not three, articles.
8The most recent literature on Holmes includes: Burton, Justice Holmes and the Jesuits
(1982) 27 Am. J. Jurisprudence 32; Bogen, Free Speech Metamorphosis of Mr. Justice Holnes
and the Jesuits (1982) 27 Am.J. Jurisprudence 32; Touster, Holmes a Hundred Years Ago: The
Common Law and Legal Theory (1982) 10 Hofstra L. Rev. 673; Gorden, Hohnes’ Common
Law as Legal and Social Science (1982) 10 Hofstra L. Rev. 719; White, The Integrity of Hohnes’
Jurisprudence (1982) 10 Hofstra L. Rev. 633; Monagan, Holmes’Common Law: An Originating
Venture (1981) 67 A.B.A.J. 312; Lundquist, Oliver Wendell Holmnes and External Standards of
Criminal and Tort Liability Application of Theory on the Massachusetts Bench (1979) 28 Buffalo
L. Rev. 607.
For a sampling of the recent literature on realism see: Note, ‘Round and ‘Round the Bramble
Bush: From LegalRealism to Critical Legal Scholarship (1982) 95 Harv. L. Rev. 1669; Schlegel,
American Legal Realism and Empirical Social Science: The Singular Case of Underhill Moore
(1980) 29 Buffalo L. Rev. 195; Tushnet, Post-Realist Legal Scholarship [1980] Wis. L. Rev.
1383; Schlegel, American Legal Realism and Empirical Social Science: From the Yale Expe-
rience (1975) 28 Buffalo L. Rev. 459; Lyons, Legal Formalism and Instrumentalism – A Path-
ological Study (1981) 66 Cornell L. Rev. 949; Rumble, The Legal Positivism of John Austin
and the Realist Movement in American Jurisprudence (1981) 66 Cornell L. Rev. 986; Golding,
Realism and Functionalism in the Legal Thought of Felix S. Cohen (1981) 66 Cornell L. Rev.
1032; and J.W. Johnson, American Legal Culture, 1908-1940 (1981).
9Llewellyn, “A Realistic Jurisprudence – The Next Step” in K. Llewellyn, Jurisprudence
(1962) 3, 29. Llewellyn was fond of eulogizing Holmes and was wont, on occasion, to deify
him. For example, in 1935, he wrote as his opening paragraph of “Holmes” in Jurisprudence,
513:
Men reflect institutions. Men are made of the institutions they have grown into,
absorbed in whole or in part, and recombined into an individual personality. But
to some men it is given themselves to become an institution. Holmes molds America.
But Llewelyn was not alone, nor was he the first in such profuse praise. See the “Appendix”
1984]
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
Writing about Oliver Wendell Holmes can be likened to playing Hamlet in the
theatre: It is a kind of apprenticeship that [American] legal scholars undertake
as a way of measuring their fitness to endure the academic travails ahead.’0
Perhaps it is closer to the truth to say that it is through the persistent
reassessment and re-interpretation of the thought of the ageless Holmes that
each generation of American lawyers begins to understand and express, and
on occasion polemicize, its own version of truth in American law. The
recurrent references to the “Olympian” are either to give the proferred ver-
sion of truth the credibility of that pre-eminent American authority or, less
frequently, to assault him as the incarnation of all that is wrong, ethically
or ideologically, in American Law.II
This longstanding preoccupation with Holmes has been complemented
recently by a resurgence of interest in the American realist movement. Much
modern scholarship in this vein has, perhaps naturally, identified Holmes
as the intellectual progenitor of the realist gospel.’ 2 Some of that writing
appears intended to reassess and consolidate the substantial contributions
made by legal realism to modern American positivist thought.’ 3 Indeed,
to Llewellyn, Holmes (1935) 35 Colum. L. Rev. 485, 490-2, for a compendium of literature
on Holmes up to 1935. See also H.C. Shriver, What Justice Holmes Wrote, and What Has
Been Written About Him: A Bibliography, 1866-1976 (1978). In addition, see the summaries
of the history of Holmes’ hagiography in G. Edward White, “The Rise and Fall of Mr. Justice
Holmes” in Patterns of American Legal Thought (1978) 174, and in Touster, supra, note 8,
673.
1White supra, note 8, 633.
“Gorden’s article, supra, note 8, is an outstanding example of a reassessment of Holmes’
jurisprudence that appears to be intended as somewhat polemical. It is also one of the most
interesting and thought-provoking of the recent reassments. Recent American legal scholarship
demonstrates that Holmes can be cited in support of nearly all of America’s perspectives on
law. Currently, the economics-and-law movement cites Holmes frequently, largely, it appears,
out of a desire to give their somewhat skewed view of legal and moral reality a pedigree and
perhaps a credibility it might otherwise lack in America. Upon reflection though it is not
surprising that Holmes can be cited in support of a vast body of American jurisprudential
thought, since the philosophical foundation of most American jurisprudence is, like the phil-
osophical basis of Holmes’ thinking itself, predominantly utilitarian and pragmatic in orientation.
‘ ‘Naturally” because the realists treated Holmes in this way themselves. The best and most
interesting accounts of the American realist movement are: E. Purcell Jr., The Crises of Dem-
ocratic Theory: Scientific Naturalism and the Problems of Vahle (1973) 159-78; G. Gilmore,
The Ages of American Law (1977); W. Twining, Karl Llewellyn and the Realist Movement
(1973); W Rumble, Jr., American Legal Realism: Skepticism, Reform and the Judicial Process
(1968); A. Hunt, The Sociological Movement in Law (1978) 1-60; Currie, The Materials of Law
Study (1950-51) 3 J. Legal Education 331; and Currie, The Materials of Law Study (1955-56)
8 J. Legal Education 1. Perhaps the precursor to all these is M. White, Social Thought in
America: The Revolt Against Formalism (Boston: Beacon Press, 1949).
‘3See, e.g., Lyons, supra, note 8, and ‘Round and ‘Round the Bramble Bush: From Legal
Realism to Critical Legal Scholarship, supra, note 8.
McGILL LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 29
this seems to be the thrust of Robert Summers’ work. A few of the more
interesting studies associated with this resurgence examine the phenomenon
of legal realism in an historical and social context. 14 Others seek to determine
where the apparent predisposition to ethical relativism and consequential-
ism of legal realism and analytical positivism have left modem American
legal scholarship.15
However engaging and thought-provoking the best of these recent stud-
ies may be, they all exhibit a somewhat solipsistic view of legal reality: they
are manifestly American in their liberal view of what counts in the world.
This disposition is not, in itself, particularly objectionable until it is noticed
that a view of law developed in a peculiarly American context in response
to peculiarly American phenomena is offered by some of these authors as
a near-comprehensive explanation of what appears to be a starkly mono-
lithic idea of law. Professor Summers’ contribution on Holmes and Amer-
ican legal realism exhibits marked tendencies in this direction, and in this
respect his work is remarkably parochial.
The social and academic conditions of American legal realism will be
considered briefly below. For the moment it is sufficient to observe that
time and place played a principal role in the development of this body of
ideas about law. As a consequence, it is only in a context of time and place
that one can and should attempt to understand them. Moreover, the peculiar’
conditions of the growth of this body of ideas about law make it difficult,
if not impossible, to abstract from it any general and universally applicable
propositions about law. Quintessentially modem-American ideas about right
and wrong, the possibility of human knowledge, and the nature of man and
society form the very foundation of the legal philosophy exhibited in Amer-
ican legal realism. In his elaboration of the pragmatic and instrumental
aspects of that philosophy, Summers often fails to observe and respect the
limits that the cultural contingency of ideas places on their translatability.
As I will argue later, Summers’ study of American legal realism is marred
in general by a failure to examine and come to terms with his own and his
subject’s epistemological, ethical and social preconceptions.
Summers’ enterprise is misdirected in another respect. Pragmatic in-
strumentalism is incongruously offered by Summers as America’s answer
to analytical positivism, natural law theory and historical jurisprudence. It
1
4See, e.g., Schlegel, American Legal Realism and Empirical Social Science: The Singular
Case of Underhill Moore, supra, note 8, and Schlegel, American Legal Realism and Empirical
Social Science: From the Yale Experience, supra, note 8.
15See, e.g., Purcell, supra, note 12, and Leff, Economic Analysis of Law: Some Realism about
Nominalism (1974) 60 Va L. Rev. 451, 453 et seq.
1984]
BOOK REVIEWS
is, he claims, ” a fourth great tradition in Western legal theory”. 16 There is
something unfortunate and, as it turns out, particularly foreboding in these
assertions. Summers appears to view jurisprudence as a positivist legal theorist
might view a legal system, composed of discrete and identifiable units or
divisions of thought, which behave like concrete objects in the material
world. Accordingly, the realm of juris-consults is populated by analytical
positivists who “have analyzed the basic concepts that figure in a system
of law”, natural law theorists, who “have concentrated on notions of the
‘right’ and the ‘good’ to be realized through law”, and historical jurists, who
“have addressed the factors that influence law’s content at any given time,
the stages of law’s evolution, its modes of growth and change and so on.”17
I found this taxonomy to be disappointing in its dismissive reduction of
philosophical and sociological thought about law to three static categories.18
Behind it lies a positivist’s comprehension.
Law, for Summers, is a system of abstract concepts. Positivism defines
and delimits the concepts, and describes and critically analyzes the concep-
tual system in which they are contained. Historical jurisprudence explains
the social origins of the “content” of the concepts. Natural law discerns
whether the “content” is “good” or “bad”, “right” or “wrong”. Instrumen-
talism, the emergent fourth school, teaches its students how to manipulate
the legal concepts in judicial and social “space”. Thus, in Summers’ uni-
verse, two schools focus upon content and two schools focus upon form.
Such austerity betrays a superficiality in perception which, unfortunately,
characterizes much of Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory. Even
accepting the relevance of the taxonomy, Summers’ notion of pragmatic
instrumentalism is a species of positivism. It is grounded firmly in the
conviction that the “is” in law is entirely distinct from the “ought” and
that the analysis of the concepts, or in his case the instruments, in the
‘6Summers, supra, note 1, 19. One is reminded here of the (perhaps unfair) characterization
by Grant Gilmore, supra, note 12, 78, of William Twining’s thesis:
Indeed Professor Twinning suggests, by implication, that Legal Realism was, so to
say, a play-off for the Ivy League championship, with the combined faculties of the
Columbia and Yale Law Schools taking the field against Harvard.
Twining’s thesis can be found in Twining, supra, note 12, 10-83, 375-87.
17Summers, supra, note 1, 20.
181 should emphasize that the taxonomy itself is quite common and, by itself, unobjectionable.
Categories and taxonomies are, or at least ought to be, designed for particular uses and purposes.
My objection to Summers’ use of this taxonomy is twofold: first, he appears to believe that if
something is categorized it is comprehended and therefore unworthy of further consideration
and, second, he appears to believe that without having articulated the purpose of his list, it is
a significant endeavour to attempt to add pragmatic instrumentalism to it.
REVUE DE DROIT DE McGILL
[Vol. 29
consequently autonomous legal system is an inherently worthwhile pas-
time.’9 Moreover, the presentation of this aspect of Summers’ thesis is a
portent of stylistic things to come. At an early stage in the book the tax-
onomical list, as the principal vehicle of analysis and demonstration, is first
used to testify to the simplicity ofjurisprudential thought itself. This vehicle
reappears under many guises to perform numerous tasks for which it is not
suited.
I. Pragmatic Instrumentalism in American Legal Thought
Pragmatic instrumentalism is the name used by Summers to designate
a body of thinking about law that he claims developed in America in the
first four decades of the twentieth century. It otherwise might fairly and
succinctly be described as American sociological jurisprudence, without the
sociology, and American legal realism without the extreme behaviourism
and moral skepticism of the likes of Underhill Moore, Herman Oliphant,
Jerome Frank or Judge Joseph C. Hutchinson. 20 Its central statement is that
law is an instrument of social control. In its instrumental aspects the theory
wants to ask, chiefly, how law can be made more valuable and useful as a
tool in the “hands of officials and practical men of affairs”. 2′ The pragmatic
complement of this view is the assertion that the law is instrumental to
ends that are “fact” or “context” specific. Occasionally, asserts Summers,
the “instrumental facets of legal phenomena” are directed towards purposes
19H.L.A. Hart distinguished at least five meanings of positivism “bandied about in contem-
porary jurisprudence”. Principal among these is the view that “there is no necessary connection
between law and morals, or law as it is and ought to be”, and the view that the “analysis …
of legal concepts is (a) worth pursuing and (b) to be distinguished from historical inquiries
into the causes or origins of laws, from sociological inquiries into the relation of law and other
social phenomena and from criticism or appraisal of law whether in terms of morals, social
aims, functions, or otherwise”: Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals (1958)
71 Harv. L. Rev. 593, 601-2, note 25.
20For an example of the application of behaviourist psychology in law, see Moore, Rational
Basis of Legal Institutions (1923) 23 Colum. L. Rev. 609 wherein Moore described legal in-
stitutions in terms of human behavior, “the happening over and over again of the same kind
of behavior”. Moore argued, at page 613, that “[t]he study of legal institutions must begin with
the motivation of habit formation, stabilization, modification, and obliteration, with the ‘drives’,
whether instinctive or otherwise, which motivate one to behave habitually, and the impulses
which push in another direction”. Here, he asserted, “the psychologists are ready to assist with
formulations and facts”. White, Patterns, supra, note 9, and Rumble, supra, note 12, develop
the thesis, probably correct, that a strong strain of behaviourist psychology runs through all
of the works of the leading realists and serves to mark them off from the sociological juris-
prudents who are portrayed by White and Rumble as their historical precursors.
2’Summers, supra, note 1, 20.
1984]
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
729
that are internal to the law’s own functioning. 22 More commonly, however,
the goals of law are chosen from “outside” law. In the grander version of
the pragmatic-instrumentalist view (a version which Summers asserts was
not fully explored by the realists or sociological jurisprudents), law is de-
scribed as a means, an instrument, or a technology that lawyers use to design
institutions and to give effect to social purposes formulated through a knowl-
edge of society derived from empirical analysis. Lawyers, on this view, are
“social engineers”. In a slightly more commonplace and, one might add,
more influential version of pragmatic instrumentalism, common law law-
yers and judges are exhorted to understand their legal rules by asking how
those rules actually function in their social setting rather than whether and
how they conform to a logically coherent conceptual order. Legal rules are
conceived of as the tools of legal reasoning and not as the maxims of an
axiomatic system, and lawyers and judges are regarded as officials manip-
ulating those tools to settle private disputes and arrange or legitimate private
affairs.
Instrumentalist thinking in legal theory, as Professor Summers rightly
points out, is not at all peculiar to American legal realism or American
sociological jurisprudence. Herman Oliphant, for example, in a passage cited
by Summers, acknowledged the American realists’ debt to Jeremy Bentham:
“A century ago, Jeremy Bentham saw law not as an ultimate but merely as
a means to an end and argued that it should be scientifically exploited as
such”. 23 Most of the other realists acknowledged, or would have acknowl-
edged, a similar debt.24 Nor is there much doubt that Rudolph von Ihering
had, in this and several other key respects, a similar influence on the de-
velopment and shape of instrumentalist thinking in American jurisprud-
ence. 25 In The Spirit of the Common Law, Pound acknowledged that Ihering’s
22Summers, supra, note 1, 74 et seq. For example, one might want to agree with Summers
(and apparently argue against his instrumentalists – Summers, supra, note 1, 22) that there
are certain goals inherent in the adjudicative process that dictate or establish the goals of
adjudicative law. At page 74, Summers says: “The instrumentalists did not explicitly recognize
that the law itself can be a source and definer of goals. Rather, most of them appear to have
assumed simply that particular forms of law draw all their goals from external sources such
as democratic processes and the advice of experts in the so-called policy sciences – economics,
sociology, political science, social psychology, and the like.”
23 Oliphant, The New Legal Education (1930) 131 The Nation 495, quoted by Summers,
supra, note 1, 60.
24See, e.g., Llewellyn, “A Realistic Jurisprudence – The Next Step”, supra, note 9, 29.
25Compare the following indictment levelled at Karl Llewellyn by Lon Fuller in his article,
American Legal Realism (1934) 82 U. Pa L. Rev. 429, 449, note 46:
The citation of authorities is so often a form of intellectual exhibitionism that one
hesitates to criticize a man who is free from this ostentation. Yet it does seem to
me that Llewellyn errs too far in the opposite direction. I am particularly distressed
at the absence of reference to that great pioneer among “realists”, Rudolph von
Ihering. There are a number of places in Llewellyn’s writings where Ihering’s views
McGILL LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 29
conception of law as “a means toward social ends, [his] doctrine that law
exists to secure interests, social, public, and individual was of enduring value
for legal science”. 26 But there is an even richer tradition to instrumentalist
thinking in law than this. One could cite passages from thinkers ranging
from Aquinas to Hobbes to the effect that law is in some ways instrumental
to purposes, whether social, human or divine. What is peculiar about Amer-
ica’s turn-of-the-century variety ofinstrumentalism are the assumptions that
animated it.
Summers’, and America’s, version of instrumentalism is pragmatic and
utilitarian: it makes law an instrument for the resolution of particular prob-
lems in particular contexts to ends that are chosen by means of a felicific
calculus. Summers’ pragmatic instrumentalism asserts (re-iterating William
James’ statement that truth is a function of “last things, fruits, conse-
quences”) that:
[i]deas are to be tested in terms of the difference they make for possible human
experience. Brute facts, not abstractions, have primacy, and the brute facts of
experience reveal a social reality that is highly plural. It consists of an immense
variety of concepts and functional relationships. Problems arise out of these
contexts and relations, and solutions are relative to and dependent upon them.27
The concomitant ethical theory, Summers observes in an elaboration of
Holmes’ “felt necessities of the time”, is that:
the social order should respect the existing wants of the day and that when
such wants conflict, choices should be made that will maximize satisfactions
all around. Existing wants emerge from discrete contexts. These contexts, not
ideology, control value, and specific questions of value can be very largely
reduced to empirical questions of fact.28
The social theory informing Summers’ pragmatic instrumentalism, al-
though seldom explicitly articulated or investigated by the theorists them-
selves (or, remarkably, by Summers) is probably classical liberal in pedigree.
Law, for example, was not perceived as an instrument of class oppression
or a reflection of the economic relations of a class society. Nor was law seen
as the instrument of a just or natural social order. Rather, for these theorists
law was a decidedly neutral force in the prevailing social arrangements.
almost intrude themselves. Llewellyn seems sometimes to imply that prior to Amer-
ican legal realism it had never occurred to anyone to question the “ideology” of
the law, or to inquire whether it coincided with the real motivation of legal rules.
Yet most of Ihering’s life was devoted to ferreting out the social reality concealed
behind the “ideology” of the Roman Law.
26R. Pound, The Spirit of Common Law (Boston: Beacon Press, 1963) 205.
27Summers, supra, note 1, 31.
28Summers, supra, note 1, 32.
1984]
BOOK REVIEWS
This posture seems implicit in the theory’s assertion that law ought to
be guided in its instrumentality by the “felt necessities of the time”: law is
mere technology; it implements and facilitates; it does not constitute or
generate. Law is the form to which society gives the content. Legal theorists,
on this view, are confined in their social theorizing to determining what the
“felt necessities of the time” demand of law. In Karl Llewellyn’s words:
Law and the law official are not therefore in one real sense what makes order
in society. For them society is given and order is given because society is
given. … The law, then, the interference of officials in disputes, appears as
the means of dealing with disputes which do not otherwise get settled. Less as
making order than as maintaining order when it has gotten out of order. …
By and large the basic order of our society and for that matter in any society
is not produced by law. … Law plays only on the fringes. 29
Perhaps another way to put this point is to draw an analogy between the
pragmatic instrumentalist’s conception of law and the classical liberal econ-
omists’ conception of economic relations in a free-market economy. Ad-
vocates of both views posit an independent object of study –
law in one
case and economic relations in the other – and both advocate what purports
to be a value-neutral, scientific investigation and explanation of their object
of study.30 When pressed, advocates of both views assert that the facet of
society which each seeks to understand, explain and occasionally justify is
truly governed by natural forces –
in law, the “felt necessities of the time”,
in market relations, the utility curves of individual transactors – which are
beyond control and manipulation and, most crucially, beyond question.
This posture may seem a rather curious one for a theory whose central
tenet is that law is an instrument of social control. After all, one quite
legitimately might ask: Who or what is controlling this instrument? Who
or what makes it go? It seems that beyond responding, “the felt necessities
of the time”, America’s pragmatic instrumentalists were not interested in
29K. Llewellyn, The Bramble Bush (1951) 21, 110. To be fair to Llewellyn, this is somewhat
of an oversimplification of his view, but it is representative of at least the thrust of much of
what he said and thought about law.
30’Science” is a legitimating word in America. It was frequently on the lips and pens of the
realists and their predecessors in American legal thought, the so-called “formalists”. Notions
of science and scientific inquiry vary from age to age. For example, one can contrast the legal
science of Holmes (discussed in Gorden, supra, note 8) and the science of Underhill Moore
(described in Schlegel, American Legal Realism and Empirical Social Science: The Singular
Case of Underhill Moore, supra, note 8) or Cook, Scientific Method and the Law (1927) 13
A.B.A.J. 303. But from age to age its truth-conferring function remains the same. To the realists,
“science” lent the aura of objectivity and value-neutrality to the version of law they sought to
propogate. It continues to do so today for the economics-and-law movement.
REVUE DE DROIT DE McGILL
[Vol. 29
pursuing this or related questions. 3′ They were, in spite of their ostensible
anti-establishment proclivities and iconoclastic fervour, affirmers and sup-
porters of the social status quo.32 This is, of course, a difficult claim to
substantiate. It is asserted on the basis of a near-total lack of social theorizing
(as opposed to empirical social research) in the writings of the legal lights
of the realist and sociological jurisprudence movement. 33 It is appropriate
to ask why these lawyers did not pursue the logic of an instrumental con-
ception of law and reach the obvious questions of whose instrument the
law was, or whether the goals pursued through law were, for example, con-
ducive to a just or natural social order. My tentative response (for Summers
apparently did not think to ask such questions) is that to have engaged in
this inquiry might have led, ineluctably, to an undermining of the theory
itself.34 In a utilitarian world-view, law must be a value-neutral, non-ide-
ological and apolitical arbiter of interests, allowing the social order to be
31Other American variations on the instrumentalist theme place more substantial emphasis
on the relation between social and economic power structures and the instrumentality of law.
The work ofJ. Willard Hurst is a prime example of such a variation, as are the contemporary
derivatives of Hurst’s scholarship, such as M. Horwitz, The Transformation ofAmnerican Law
1780-1860 (1977).
32Rather like The Right Honourable Lord Denning of Whitchurch.
33This, in effect, is substantially the same charge that Llewellyn boldly levelled at Pound:
see Llewellyn, “A Realistic Jurisprudence – The Next Step”, supra, note 9, 708, note 3.
Llewellyn observed that, insightful as Pound’s scholarship might have been, it ultimately lacked
the conviction of its sociological pretensions. Thus, said Llewellyn, “[slociologicaljurisprudence
remains bare of most that is significant in sociology.”
Similarly, it is difficult to see how, when all is said and done, the realists themselves advanced
the cause of exposing the “inter-relation” of law and society. Most of their scholarship was
devoted to court-centered analysis of law and the advancement and elucidation of their own
peculiar jurisprudential thesis. Perhaps, however, their belabouring the point about the inde-
terminacy of rules has made subsequent generations of American lawyers question the ideo-
logical content of American law. In this respect, the realists might be considered the precursors
of the Critical Legal Studies movement: see, infra, note 35.
34Lon Fuller’s demonstration that a “command” theory of law is a necessary part of any
theory of law that posits an absolute distinction between law and morality is pertinent here.
Of John Austin’s reluctance to abandon that tenet of the positivist creed Fuller wrote in his
article, Positivism and Fidelity to Law – A Reply to Professor Hart (1958) Harv. L. Rev. 630,
640:
All of these problems [concerning the command theory of law] Austin sees with
varying degrees of explicitness, and he struggles mightily with them. Over and over
again he teeters on the edge of an abandonment of the command theory in favour
of what Professor Hart has described as a view that discerns the foundations of a
legal order in certain fundamental accepted rules specifying the essential lawmaking
procedures. Yet he never takes the plunge. He does not take it because he had a
sure insight that it would forfeit the black-and-white distinction between law and
morality that was the whole object of his Lectures….
Similarly, any serious investigation into the goals of law or into the question of who controls
the instrumentality of law, of who or what “commands”, would as surely result in the under-
mining of the description of law as “lawyers’ means” and the forfeiture of the distinction that
the realists, like their formalist predecessors, made betwen law and morality. In brief, the
realists’ version of the means/end dichotomy is an incarnation of the law/morality dichotomy.
The point of making the dichotomy is to allow legal philosophers to fix their gaze upon the
1984]
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
constituted by the natural mechanisms of market forces. Individuals must
be left reasonably free from external constraints so that they can pursue the
maximization of their individual interests. To the extent that one admits
that law is manipulable by anything larger than “interests in context” (for
example, by a social class), one denies the possibility of a social order con-
stituted by natural forces, and, as a consequence, one denies the ideological,
or at least political, neutrality of law. To the extent that one admits that
law is instrumental in the formation and constitution of social order, one
denies its very instrumentality (because tools do not constitute) and there-
fore its value-neutrality (because in denying its instrumentality, one must
also deny the possibility of the complete separation of law and morals). The
confinement of law’s instrumentality, therefore, to techniques of dispute
settlement and the arrangement and design of legal institutions had, for
America’s pragmatic instrumentalists, the perhaps unconscious intention of
fostering the utilitarian facade of a value-neutral, non-ideological and apol-
itical legal system.
It is worth pointing out at this stage that in this, as in several other key
respects to be mentioned presently, realism and sociological jurisprudence,
or Summers’ pragmatic instrumentalism, did not differ markedly from the
so-called (American) legal formalism which preceded it and which served
rather conveniently as its whipping-boy. Indeed, if one were looking for
continuity in twentieth-century American legal thought, one might find it
here. Perhaps the most obvious explanation for what occurred in American
legal thought in the 1920s, 1930s and 1940s is that a system of thought was
developed which had the ultimate effect and, possibly, end of preserving
the apparent neutrality of law.35
means of law to the exclusion of its ends. Seriously reconsidering the ends of law would
eventually lead to the realization that the dichotomy is false and that the exercise of focusing
merely on the means is misconceived. See Fuller, “Means and Ends” in K. Winston, ed., The
Principles of Social Order (1981) 47-64.
35As a generalization, I think these observations are true enough of the vast bulk of realist
and sociological jurisprudence literature. I do not mean to suggest, however, that this literature
is totally devoid of social theorizing, investigations of the relationship of law to society or law
and ideology. Karl Llewellyn (see the discussion in Twining, supra, note 12, 170-202) and Felix
Cohen made significant contributions in this direction. The suggestion is simply that most of
these legal scholars, like many of their historians, quite naturally accepted without enquiry the
liberal assumptions of their age and their nation. They did not question seriously the role of
law in a liberal democracy. Mensch, “The History of Mainstream Legal Thought” in D. Kairys,
ed., The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique (1982) paints a remarkably different picture.
For her, legal realism stands as the direct intellectual antecedent to the Critical Legal Studies
movement in its total annihilation of the pretence that the American legal system was, or could
be, objective or value-neutral. My reading of events does not entirely persuade me that legal
realism had any such effect. If it did, one might ask why the point has to be made afresh, and
with such zeal, in the 1980s. Rather, I suggest that the most significant contribution of realism
was the regeneration of court law in America by making legal explanations and justifications
more harmonious with the social and economic relations of twentieth-century American so-
ciety. That is the significance of the “functional” approach to law.
McGILL LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 29
II. From Logical Coherence to Functional Coherence
Once one accepts that the utilitarian model of a legal order –
a value-
neutral, non-ideological and apolitical system of dispute settlement (the
commonplace view) and institutional design (the grand view) –
is an in-
telligent and profitable way to conceive of law, one’s focus as an academic
lawyer naturally shifts from law as politics, law as morality, or law as ide-
ology to law as “legal system”. In turn, one’s commitment to law as legal
system comes to animate a desire to describe and understand, and occa-
sionally to justify, the integrity of that system. It seems to be the case, or
to have been the case, that in America a preponderance of activity in the
legal system is undertaken by institutions established to settle private dis-
putes. The bulk of this private dispute settlement is done by courts. Thus
most of the projects taken up by academic lawyers operating under the
influence of utilitarian theory predictably entail trying to describe and un-
derstand the process of court-centered dispute settlement. Such writers often
seem to forget that this work is predicated on the acceptance of some rather
important assumptions. They even come to regard the mechanisms of dis-
pute settlement associated with courts as “law”. A great deal of the writing
Summers has tapped to generate his theory of pragmatic instrumentalism,
and much of the theory itself, focuses on “law” in precisely this sense.
Indeed, although the American legal realists made other important contri-
butions to legal theory, it would not be unfair to observe that the essence
of realistic jurisprudence was its vigorous concern with a realistic and, for
its time, radical description of the decision-making process of American
courts. It is worthwhile, then, to digress briefly into a discussion of the
realists’ description of court-law in America. Such a digression should be
helpful to an understanding of the philosophical underpinnings and histor-
ical causes of the germ of thought about law which ostensibly provoked
Summers to formulate his theses about legal theory in America.
Like their predecessors, the so-called formalists of Christopher Colum-
bus Langdell’s era, American lawyers of the early twentieth century appar-
ently felt compelled to explain and rationalize their own body of court law.
By their time such a vast body of decisional law had been generated in the
United States that theories which emphasized the formal, logical and ra-
tional aspects of the common law decision-making process made limited
sense. Such theories no longer were capable of providing an accurate account
1984]
BOOK REVIEWS
of what actually was happening in American common law courts. 36 In the
face of the rising number of contradictory judicial pronouncements rendered
in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, the strategy of the so-
called formalists was to deny the validity of aberrant decisions and exag-
gerate the rational integrity of their positive legal order. In his typically
excessive style, Jerome Frank described that survival strategy thus:
in the decisions of the courts –
Law as he [the “Bealist”, Frank’s archetypical formalist] and his fellow men
encounter it in practical effect –
conflicts
with what he desires law to be. Wherefore he strives by the use of empty but
mouth-filling words so to represent law to himself that it will be unburdened
by what he considers the crude courtroom actualities that thwart his desires.
The method of the wishful metaphysician, who so describes the universe by
discreet omissions as to satisfy his personal longings, is of a piece with that of
Beale & Co. in defining the law. 37
According to Frank and other realists, the formalists spurned inconsistent
and contradictory decisions in order to maintain and preserve their positive
conceptual order.38 The realists, in response, rejected the positive conceptual
order in order to accept and explain contradictory decisions.
By the late 1920s and early 1930s the realists became engaged in a full-
scale assault on their caricature of the formalist tradition of, first, treating
law as a logically coherent and comprehensive body of rules and, second,
viewing the judicial decision as a statement of reasons logically deduced
from that body of rules. In the former context, they were inspired by Holmes’
prediction theory of law and Pound’s distinction between “law in books”
and “law in action”. Enough has been said about this relationship elsewhere
to make discussion of it here unnecessary. 39 In the latter, they were inspired
chiefly by John Dewey’s writing on what he called an instrumental or ex-
perimental logic, a logic Dewey contrasted critically with the formalists’
36This is Grant Gilmore’s thesis: see Gilmore, supra, note 12, 68 et seq. Johnson, supra, note
8, 65-8, suggests that it was the empirical (not juridical) information explosion of the new
social and behavioural sciences that caused the crisis.
37J. Frank, Law and the Modern Mind (New York: Tudor Publishing Co., 1936) 61. At page
56, Frank excuses his intemperate attitude towards what he referred to as “Bealistic” thought
as follows: “The slightly excessive language is to be explained perhaps by the writer’s effort to
rid himself of Bealistic tendencies to which he, like most lawyers, is subject.”
38An interesting question is what the “formalists’ criteria of choice were in their identifi-
cation of the “anomalous” decisions. I suppose one’s answer to this kind of question must
depend on the school of explanations to which one subscribes. Do we look for material, eco-
nomic, ideological, rational, formal, or logical causes to explain how a Bealist might have
chosen to incorporate one decision or one rule in his positive legal order, and exclude another?
The theories abound.
39Rumble, supra, note 12 and Gilmore, supra, note 12, 68 et seq. See also the articles cited
in the second paragraph of note 8.
REVUE DE DROITDE McGILL
[Vol. 29
syllogistic logic of demonstration. Preferring the former to the latter, Dewey
described the problem-solving technique of common law lawyers, thus:
No lawyer ever thought out the case of a client in terms of the syllogism. He
begins with a conclusion which he intends to reach, favorable to his client of
course, and then analyzes the facts of the situation to find material out of which
to construct a favorable statement of facts, to form a minor premise. At the
same time he goes over recorded cases to find rules of law employed in cases
which can be presented as similar, rules which will substantiate a certain way
of looking at and interpreting the facts. And as his acquaintance with rules of
law judged applicable widens, he probably alters perspective and emphasis in
selection of the facts which are to form his evidential data. And as he learns
more of the facts of the case he may modify his selection of rules of law upon
which he bases his case. 40
Similarly, Dewey argued that judicial decision-making is best described
as the process of using legal rules to reason to a conclusion. Once that
conclusion has been reached, the judicial decision-maker sets about the task
ofjustifying his decision and demonstrating its legal soundness by drafting
a decision in the logico-deductive mode. Wrote Dewey:
Courts not only reach decisions; they expound them, and the exposition must
state justifying reasons. The mental operations therein involved are somewhat
different from those involved in arriving at a conclusion. The logic of exposition
is different from [the logic of] search and inquiry. In the latter, the situation
as it exists is more or less doubtful, indeterminate, and problematic with respect
to what it signifies. It unfolds itself gradually and is susceptible of dramatic
surprise, at all events it has, for the time being, two sides. Exposition implies
that a definitive solution is reached, that the situation is now determinate with
respect to its legal implication. Its purpose is to set forth grounds for the
decision reached so that it will not appear as an arbitrary dictum, and so that
it will indicate a rule for dealing with similar cases in the future.41
This new model of the judicial decision was the necessary corollary of
a legal philosophy that denied the central importance of the “law in books” 42
and assaulted “the Holy Grail of a coherent, comprehensive system of rules
and principles”. 43 It sought to emphasize the indeterminacy of legal rules
by describing the common law decision-making process as one of search
and inquiry rather than pure deduction, and legal rules as the instrument
of that search process. The myth of conceptual certainty in law was replaced
by the earnest belief that legal decisions ought to be made by discerning the
social functions, purposes or goals (as determined, ultimately, by the felt
40Dewey, Logical Method and Law (1924) 10 Cornell L.Q. 7, 23.
41Ibid., 24.
42R. Pound, Law in Books and Law in Action (1910) 44 Am. L. Rev. 35.
43This is Frank’s colourful characterization for a “common disease of the mind” that afflicted
most of his generation of lawyers and law teachers: Frank, supra, note 37.
1984]
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
necessities of the time) of the array of possibly applicable rules in any par-
ticular situation. The pragmatic assertion that it was a lawyer’s job to predict
the imposition of state sanctions through courts had the effect of encouraging
lawyers to take a harder, more objective look at the way they actually rea-
soned in law. Together, these related ideas formed the basis of the realist
perspective on court law and, together, they form the fundamental inspi-
ration for Robert Summers’ theory of pragmatic instrumentalism. Summers
has a good deal to offer in the expounding of his theory, including obser-
vations in a similarly instrumental vein on the design and operation of legal
institutions and institutional structures other than courts. Of this aspect of
his book more will be said below. For now, I would offer an observation
or two about the significance of these ideas.
It bears repeating that realism and formalism are identical in their
assertion that a legal order is value-neutral, non-ideological and apolitical.
This observation can be developed by adding that realism and formalism
also are exactly the same in their preoccupation with court-law and in their
concern with validating the processes of court-law in America. This latter
conclusion is indicated in two basic ways. First, despite some of the fearful
blustering, it seems doubtful that many of the realists seriously rejected the
principle that their law ought to be, in some measure, conceptually coherent
and certain. Rather, the seemingly out-of-hand rejection of the “fictitious
unity of the law”, bolstered by Dewey’s model of the judicial decision, was
largely mere posturing. It had the convenient rhetorical effect of making
American lawyers.become aware (again) that their law was, in a very relevant
way, connected with the day-to-day affairs of their nation. Second, and more
important, even to the extent that the strictures of the realists were consid-
ered to have been “radical” by the less sanguine of America’s legal academics
of the 1930s and 1940s, from the perspective of fifty years the phenomenon
of American legal realism seems best characterized as an effort merely to
remodel and revamp an outmoded conceptual order that was atrophying
from the effects of an overzealous formalism, rather than as the revolution
in legal theory that many of its American historians have described.
Faced with the “fictitious unity of the law” the American legal realists
sought to regenerate the common law of the United States by advocating a
principle of coherence which emphasized the connection between the con-
ceptual order and the daily affairs of their nation. Logical coherence in law
was therefore to be invigorated by functional coherence. The realists ex-
horted American lawyers to look for the unity and intelligibility of their
legal rules not in the principles of logical entailment, but in the socio-eco-
nomic relations upon which the rules operated. Purely logical arguments
could no longer be compelling, partly because of their diminished predictive
value in the application of state power through the courts, and partly because
McGILL LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 29
the end result of any chain of deductive reasoning was, as Dewey had argued,
only as sound as the predetermined conclusion sought to be reached. It also
must have been clear to many turn-of-the-century American lawyers that
much of the doctrine that sustained the process of formalistic legal reasoning
was no longer capable of explaining, let alone predicting, the results by even
the most sophisticated notions of legal justice. In their efforts to generate a
more realistic description of, and a more functional methodology for, the
processes of American court law the realists never intended to call into
question the integrity of that system. Indeed, as is often the case with “rad-
ical” criticism, the realistic criticism of American law had the ultimate effect
of offering a new vindication for the essentials of the established utilitarian
legal order.44 That new vindication brought the language and reasoning of
American lawyers more closely into line with that of their clients, and with
the “felt necessities of the time”. Legal explanations would make “common”
sense not only to those who offered them for sale but also to those who
ultimately consumed them.45 Perhaps buried in these observations lies an
explanation for the ease with which the lessons of realistic jurisprudence
have worked their way into the consciousness of Anglo-American lawyers
in the fourth quarter of the twentieth century: the change in the meaning
of law was, in these respects, merely illusory.46
the shift from logical coherence to functional coherence –
Once the relatively minimal theoretical significance of realism is rec-
ognized –
and
the practical significance of realism is admitted –
the preservation of the
integrity of court law in America –
perhaps legal theorists can be more
“realistic” about realism’s historical causes and conditions. Perhaps, for
example, one could be so bold as to stand by the claim that the excessive
language in much of the realist literature was just the rhetoric one associates
44Lewellyn suggested as much in his “Foreword” to the second edition of The Bramble
Bush, where he said that realism “was and still is an effort at mnore effective legal reasoning”
and that it was a mistake to conceive of realism as a “philosophy”.
451n this respect the realists served a purpose very much like that which Lord Mansfield
served in the late eighteenth century. Patrick Atiyah states in his work, The Rise and Fall of
Freedom of Contract'” (1979) 122: “On the Bench, Mansfield’s objective with regard to com-
mercial law was to make the law more serviceable to the commercial community. That meant
that it must become more rational, more intelligible, more predictable, and more just according
to the standards of the mercantile world.”
It would not be implausible to claim that the Uniform Commercial Code, and, in particular
Karl Llewellyn’s Article 2 thereof, was the crowning achievement of realistic jurisprudence.
46 That the empirical and functional insights of realism have been incorporated into the
mainstream of Anglo-American positivist thought is best demonstrated in the seminal con-
tribution of H.L.A. Hart to modem positivism. See H. Hart, The Concept of Law (1961) and
W. Twining & D. Miers, How to Do Things with Rules, 2nd ed. (1982).
19841
BOOK REVIEWS
with ideologues and academics in pursuit of notoriety and tenure.47 Perhaps
also legal realism and sociological jurisprudence were animated by related
social and political themes of the partisan politics of their day. Thus, there
may be something to the thesis that the realists were, or at least were engaged
in training, the administrators of Roosevelt’s New Deal and that their legal
realism was part of a larger array of politically-motivated argumentation
designed to dislodge a locus of power in American society that subscribed,
by chance or necessity, to an excessively conceptual philosophy of law.4 8
I make no pretense of knowing whether particular ideologies of law are
associated by necessity with particular social or political ideologies. 49 What
I would assert, however, is that individuals, and indeed whole schools of
thought, do not maintain with any constancy a particular ethical or epis-
temological premise throughout each field of their opinion making. One
effect of this phenomenon is the occurence of consistencies and contradic-
tions from opinion to opinion in any one individual’s thought. In philo-
sophical discourse, demonstrating the lack of such systematic consistency
is often the most cogent line of attack on a body of ideas. Philosophers, as
a consequence, spend a great deal of energy working out the internal co-
herence of their ideas. In addition, because they realize that the integrity of
their systems ultimately depends on the strength of the argumentation sup-
porting their most fundamental premises, philosophers are usually careful
to work out that argumentation in some detail. They are aware that the
integrity of their thought depends on the strength of its foundation and the
rational coherence of its superstructure. In political discourse, systematic
integrity and the soundness of basic premises are not so highly valued. The
dynamics of partisan political discourse is, as a consequence, significantly
different. Positions are taken and destroyed less on the basis of the soundness
47 Purcell, supra, note 12, 7, notes that law-teaching as a full-time occupation had only become
widely established by the turn of the century. At page 78, Purchell notes that unlike the retired
practitioners of old, the generation of young law teachers coming into American law schools
in the first decade of the twentieth century (and the next two decades) “was expected to devote
[itself] to the dispassionate study of the law and to the improved training of his students.”
There was a great deal of self-conscious deprecation on the part of this generation of American
law teachers, especially when they compared their craft to the social sciences. Llewellyn, for
example, spoke apologetically of law as “the most backward of social disciplines”, looking over
his shoulder, no doubt, at the increasing sophistication of companion social sciences in the
university setting: Llewellyn, “Legal Tradition and Social Science Method – A Realist’s Cri-
tique” in Jurisprudence, supra, note 9, 77.
48This thesis is mentioned in White Patterns, supra, note 9, 116-35 and in Twining, supra,
note 12, 57-8. It is developed in somewhat greater detail in Hunt, supra, note 12, 38-40.
49Consider Karl Renner’s thesis in his work, The Institutions of Private Law and their Social
Functions (1949) to the effect that political ideology and social structure changed radically in
Western Europe from the middle ages to the end of the nineteenth century without at all
affecting the form and ideology of Western European law.
REVUE DE DROIT DE McGILL
[Vol. 29
of their fundamental premises or their place in a coherent body of ideas,
and more on the basis of their mere association with “discredited” opinions
or men. The paradigmatic syllogism lurking beneath much partisan political
discourse is of the form: (i) Opinion “x” is bad; (ii) Holders of opinion “x”
generally hold opinion “y”; (iii) Therefore opinion “y” is bad, or perhaps:
(i) Smith holds opinion “x”; (ii) Smith is bad; (iii) Therefore opinion “x
is bad. This state of affairs probably obtains because winning and losing an
argument in the “marketplace of ideas” usually depends more on the va-
garies of the audience’s perceptions, awareness, intelligence and interest,
than on the soundness of the views advanced.
It is evident that much of the legal literature produced in the United
States in the 1930s and 1940s tended to be in the form of partisan political
discourse. So, for example, when one’s opponent is a lawyer who objects
to workers’ compensation legislation ostensibly because it would infringe
upon the letter or spirit of America’s written constitution, an effective way
to advance the social cause of compensation schemes is to ridicule the kind
of legal reasoning that its antagonists use to advance their argument.5 0 Sim-
ilarly, a very effective way to level an opponent in a political argument is
to note the similarities between his philosophy of law and those of, say,
Hitler or Stalin. 51
The argument advanced by the realists against their caricature of the
“formalist” vision of law may thus be characterized as an argument aimed
at the weakest point of a whole association of ideas. Destroying the sybaritic
conceptualism of “formalism” was essentially an easy and, to read Frank
and Llewellyn, enjoyable task. In the political scheme of things, it may have
had the intended effect of contributing to the discreditation of the body of
political opinions that was associated with it. In strictly legal theory, there
did not have to be any substantial difference between James C. Carter and
Joseph Beale on the one hand and Karl Llewellyn and Jerome Frank on
the other. But in the context, and only in the context, of American society
and politics of the day in which these views about law were so vigorously
advanced, this relatively insignificant difference in legal theory may have
counted for a lot in political debate.
50See Pound, The Need for Sociological Jurispndence (1907) 19 Green Bag 609, cited in
White, Patterns, supra, note 9, 105-7.
51Leo Strauss’ “reductio ad Hitleram”. This is in fact what happened to the realists in the
end. Their relativistic ethics and positivist conception of law were condemmed, by association,
with the totalitarianism of Hitler. See, e.g. Lucey, Natural Law and American Legal Realism:
Their Respective Contributions to a Theory of Law in a Democratic Society (1942) 30 George-
town L.J. 493, and Palmer, Hobbes, Holmes and Hitler (1945) 31 A.B.A.J. 569. This aspect of
the realist story is chronicled in Purcell, supra, note 12, 159-78 and White, Patterns, supra,
note 9, 211-25.
1984]
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
The argument need not rest here though. Observing that the anti-for-
malist posture of men such as Pound and Llewellyn was in part motivated
by strategy in argumentation is only one aspect of the larger thesis that
realism and sociological jurisprudence were as much directed against in-
dividuals as against their views. In turn, noticing that there is a largely
unexplored political dimension to these ideas about law raises serious ques-
tions about their social contingency altogether. It is notorious among non-
American observers that Holmes, Pound, Llewellyn, Frank and Cohen were
quintessentially American in style, tone and substance of argumentation.
One therefore wants to know how their ideas about law were affected by
the partisan politics and political ideologies of their day, by contemporary
and perhaps parallel movements in American art, American literature and
American social theory. I think it is true to say that the story of American
legal realism and sociological jurisprudence is susceptible of many versions.
Unfortunately, however, the version sketched here has seldom been seri-
ously attempted and, in the hands of lawyers discussing “legal theory” (such
as Robert Summers), is virtually always ignored.
III. Summers’ Pragmatic Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory
There are two main theses in Robert Summers’ Instrumentalism and
American Legal Theory. According to the historical theme, a general coa-
lescence of thought that was the Western world’s only major example of
instrumentalist legal thinking had occurred in American legal theory by the
early 1940s. The thrust of Summers’ philosophical thesis is that instru-
mentalism is a fourth category of legal theory which, like the other three,
is intrinsically worthy of consideration. In addition to a brief preface, an
introduction and a general conclusion, the work under review is divided
into four principal parts and is organized, more or less, around these two
main theses. Parts one and two, comprising just over one-half of the book,
concentrate on a description and critique of the chief features of American
pragmatic instrumentalism. Parts three and four, comprising about one-
quarter of the whole, contain a more fully-developed instrumentalist theory
of law.
For the most part, I found the book to be poorly written. I was frequently
annoyed by obtrusive neologisms and awkward expressions –
“one-fell-
swoopism”, “robust predictivism”, “negative corollary”, “democratarian”,
“separationism”, “deductivism” – by the occasional impenetrable passage
“A theory of value is nor-
and the more frequent pedantic observation –
mative. It sets forth what ought to be the case which may differ from what
is actually the case” – by the extensive use of such indeterminate expres-
sions as “general” and by the ubiquitous list. Most annoying is the frequency
with which the word “theory” occurs; I would be truly surprised if that
McGILL LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 29
word or one of its derivatives does not appear on every single page. Summers
uses it indiscriminately to mean everything from “explanation” to
“generalization”.
More important than this, however, is the more damning criticism that
Summers’ two main theses are misconceived. Before elaborating briefly on
this point it should be acknowledged that Instrumentalism and American
Legal Theory offers many useful observations and pertinent and penetrating
criticisms of American legal realism and sociological jurisprudence. I grant,
subject to several qualifications mentioned below, that an instrumentalist
perspective on law can be useful, and that Summers’ contributions in this
respect are therefore not only quite original but even salutary. The nature
of my disagreement with Summers is more fundamental. It concerns the
underlying philosophical premises of the book –
first, that it is useful to
talk about a body of ideas abstracted completely from their social context,
and second, that what he calls “pragmatic instrumentalism” is anything
other than a species of positivism. I also take issue with the conclusions he
seeks to draw, together with those he fails to draw, from his frequently
astute observations on the American realists and sociological jurisprudents.
Summers’ theory of “pragmatic instrumentalism” is distilled from the
work of a core group of American thinkers who lived and wrote between
1897 and 1937: O.W. Holmes, John Chipman Gray, John Dewey, Roscoe
Pound, W.W. Cook, Joseph W. Bingham, W. Underhill Moore, Herman
Oliphant, Jerome Frank, Karl N. Llewellyn, and Felix D. Cohen.52 Although
he acknowledges that this list is not exhaustive, he insists that it includes
52Summers, supra, note 1, 22-3. According to Summers, pragmatic instrumentalism devel-
oped, between these dates, into the predominant mode of legal thought in the United States.
The years 1897 and 1937 are particularly important. 1897 is the date of Oliver Wendell Holmes’
call to arms in his article The Path of the Law (1897) 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457, where Holmes
declared that law is the “business” of predicting the incidence of public force through the
“instrumentality of the Courts” and in which he looked forward to the day when “political
economy” would replace “history” as the principal method of explanation of legal dogma.
1937 is the date of publication of Felix Cohen’s The Problems of a Functional Jurisprudence
(1937) 1 Mod. L. Rev. 5, in which Cohen acknowledged Holmes’ seminal contribution in The
Path of the Law to a forty-year ferment in America’s legal thought. In this article, Cohen
compared the rise of “functional jurisprudence” and the corresponding decline of “traditional
jurisprudence” to the displacement of Elucidean geometry by the geometries of Russian math-
ematician Nicolai Lobachewski and German mathematician Georg Reimann, or to the effect
of Karl Marx and dialectical materialism and the “general doctrine of social evolution” on the
writing of history (pages 55-6). Cohen defined functionalism as “the view that a thing does not
have a ‘nature’ or ‘essence’ or ‘reality’ underlying its manifestations and effects and apart from
its relations with other things; that the nature, essence or reality of a thing is its manifestations,
its effects and its relations with other things” and described its application to law as leading
to “a definition of legal concepts, rules and institutions in terms ofjudicial decisions or other
acts of state-force” (page 8). In these two articles are contained “most of the leading ideas” of
pragmatic instrumentalism, according to Summers, supra, note 1, 25.
19841
BOOK REVIEWS
most of what he terms the “classical pragmatic instrumentalists” and, in
any event, “as many figures as are needed to provide meaningful substance
to [the] analysis of the rise and continuity of [this] important American
movement”. 53 Summers describes these men as “pioneers” in legal theory
to explain the fact that they often held divergent views of law, and to per-
suade his reader that, although each did not subscribe to all the “tenets and
corollaries” of this theory, they all “underwrote” a large majority of the
theory’s leading aspects. 54 Thus, the most obvious instance of a divergence
is described
of views –
by Summers as an ‘inside’ affair”. 55 Among the “classical” figures excluded
from discussion are Charles Sanders Pierce and William James, because, as
Summers explains, they did not write on law. Excluded from the club of
classical pragmatic instrumentalists altogether are Benjamin N. Cardozo,
because he was “distinctive in his own way” and was “often critical of
instrumentalists”, and “neo-instrumentalists” Harold Lasswell and Myres
L. MacDougal, because their “most important writings were published after
1940”.56
that between Roscoe Pound and Karl Llewellyn –
Although these passages occur early in the book, and therefore one
might be willing to suspend judgment in anticipation of justifications to
come, I was struck immediately by the arbitrariness of the choice for in-
clusion in the club of pragmatic instrumentalists and the capriciousness of
the distinction between “classical” and “modern day” or “contemporary”
pragmatic instrumentalism. There is little explanation offered, for example,
for the sudden break at 1937 with the publication of Felix Cohen’s The
Problem of Functional Jurisprudence. Admittedly this observation is of no
particular moment in itself, but it clearly foreshadows what turns into a
substantial failing of the book. In the advancement of his historical theses,
Summers almost completely disregards the historical and social setting of
the ideas about law generated by the group of individuals chosen for dis-
cussion.57 The identification of a core group of individuals and the artificial
53Summers, supra, note 1, 22, 23.
54Summers, supra, note 1, 23.
55Summers, supra, note 1, 23. The famous dispute, which Grant Gilmore, supra, note 12,
78, has described as making up “as dreary a course of reading as anyone can hope to find
anywhere”, is contained primarily in two articles: Pound, The Call for a Realist Jurisprudence
(1931) 44 Harv. L. Rev. 697 and Llewellyn, Some Realism about Realism – Responding to
Dean Pound (1931) 44 Harv. L. Rev. 1222, reproduced in Llewellyn, Jurisprudence, supra,
note 9, 42. According to Gilmore’s account of the controversy, Llewellyn and Frank, contrary
to their apparent perception of events, were not the object of Pound’s criticism in The Call
for a Realist Jurisprudence and thus the whole affair had “a ‘sadly comic’ quality”: Gilmore,
supra, note 12, 136-7, note 25.
56Summers, supra, note 1, 22.
57For a meagre discussion, see the section entitled “Origins” in Summers, supra, note 1, 26-
34.
REVUE DE DROITDE McGILL
[Vol. 29
elevation of that core into a “movement” of “classical” thought is the first
significant step in that direction.
I was surprised to find that in a book entitled Instrumentalism and
American Legal Theory only eight pages are devoted to a description of the
origins of the theory, a brevity which betrays a lack of interest in the theory’s
genesis. Thus readers are advised that the theory “was partly a reaction to
certain conditions in the world of American law during the last part of the
nineteenth and the early twentieth century” and that some theorists “reacted
critically to the ‘formalisms’ that they perceived in judicial reasoning, in
legal education, and in legal theory”. Other causes, in what essentially is a
yet another list, include “a reaction against certain substantive conceptions
that underlay formalism, including laissez-faire, the notion that only the fit
should survive the competitive struggle, generalized judicial conservatism”,
the “scientific ethos of the day”, the “technological advance of the late
nineteenth and early twentieth centuries … the automobile, the electric
light, the telephone, a whole new range of business machines, and the air-
plane”, and “the philosophy of pragmatism”. 58 These comprise the principal
items on the list of causes. The balance of the book contains little reference
to the cultural, social, academic or economic origins of the theory; instead,
it is comprised largely of exegesis and analysis.
Perhaps Summers’ reply to this criticism would be that his principal
interest in the book is the development and critique of a pragmatic instru-
mentalist philosophy of law, and that he is therefore not overly concerned
with developing a truly historical description of the body of thought and
the group of men he has chosen to study. Perhaps, in short, he is not par-
ticularly interested in his historical thesis. One suspects that this may indeed
be the case, even though a good portion of the book is devoted to a de-
scription of the thought of these men. Nevertheless, to the extent that Sum-
mers is interested in an historical thesis, his failure to deal adequately with
the social context of the ideas that he discusses is quite serious. Among
other things, it contributes to a failure on his part to perceive the fundmental
similarity between the school of thought he examines and the schools of
American legal thought that preceded and followed it. It results further in
an almost naive disposition on Summers’ part to take everything his “the-
orists” said, and in particular, what they said to the formalists, seriously
and as indicative of what they literally meant. As an antidote, one has to
read but five pages of Jerome Frank’s Law and the Modern Mind59 to realize
that he must have been sitting on a tack when he wrote it. There was
obviously more to his “instrumentalist theorizing” than mere instrumentalism.
58Summers, supra, note 1, 26-34.
59Supra, note 37.
1984]
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
Further, Summers’ own account of instrumentalism in American legal
theory is analytical and conceptual to a fault. Curiously, the only criticism
which Summers anticipates in his book comes from the quarter of analytical
positivism. Yet in its discussion of pragmatic instrumentalism and in its
construction of an elaborate framework for “instrumental theorizing”, the
book exhibits all of the- faults of the austere rationalism of analytical pos-
itivism. Herein lies the great irony of Instrumentalism and American Legal
Theory: American legal realism’s most significant contribution to American
common law thought is its advocacy of a more functional approach to law,
yet in his elevation of a “classical movement of thought” Summers seems
oblivious to the lesson to be learned from this feature of realistic juris-
prudence. He does not seem to have understood the realists’ point that the
social context of an idea can shed light on its substance and on the style of
its presentation, that law is an artifact which for its elucidation requires
attention to the motives and purposes of its artisans. As a consequence,
Summers takes the form, the rhetoric and the apparent content of realism
and sociological jurisprudence at its face value.
pragmatic instrumentalism –
Leaving aside context to enter the realm of “autonomous legal theory”,
I wondered, while reading Summers’ book, whether his systematic devel-
opment of instrumental concepts is merely a reincarnation of what some
might consider to be the less objectionable facets of legal realism. Much of
the book is taken up with criticisms of some of the excesses of realism in
order, ostensibly, to preserve the realists’ central intuition that law can be
conceived of as a means to an end. The theory, it seems, requires the new
name –
in order to avoid the unpleasant
evocations of “realism”, although Summers argues strenuously that this is
not the case. He claims that pragmatic instrumentalism is a unique theory
in that it seeks to give expression to the common philosophical views un-
derlying sociological jurisprudence, pragmatism and only “certain tenets of
legal realism” that resulted in the general coalescence of thought referred
to above. It is distinct from legal realism, he asserts, not only because it
comprehends sociological jurisprudence but also because it excludes the
more “extreme” tenets of legal realism such as legal realism’s “radical value
skepticism and [its] emphasis on nonrational and even irrational factors in
the judicial process”. 60 Despite this early avowal, Summers never identifies
the theoretical basis of this excising operation except by the unhelpful as-
sertion that the radical elements of realism are radical, and thus untenable.
For example, Summers describes the pragmatic instrumentalists’ value-
theory as “utilitarian, quantitative, conventionalist and majoritarian in tenor”,
and then observes that there were a few skeptics about value, alluding to
6 Summers, supra, note 1, 37.
McGILL LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 29
an oft-cited passage from Underhill Moore as evidence of such value skep-
ticism. 6′ If what Summers means by “values” is something absolute and
fixed, it is difficult to see how the “existing wants of the day” value formula
of his pragmatic instrumentalists is any less indicative of a value skepticism
than the following passage which he locates from Moore:
Human experience discloses no ultimates. Events are related to events so that
each is at once an end and a means. Ultimates are phantoms drifting upon
the stream of day dreams. Nor are penultimate ends rational. A rational or
logical process is directed towards an end chosen before the process is begun.
The process is judging that certain means will tend to that end.62
The other argument offered by Summers for the change in name is that
more is comprehended by “pragmatic instrumentalism” than by “legal re-
alism”, so that such figures as Holmes and Gray are promoted from mere
“precursors” of American legal realism to “progenitors” of “America’s only
indigenous theory of law”. Holmes’ legal philosophy and the sociological
jurisprudence of Pound would have an altogether moderating effect on the
general theory, because, ostensibly, their theories were not (as) value skept-
ical and behaviourist in orientation. Therefore, the argument goes, if the
general theory is to include these views, it must exclude radical realism. To
make this argument work, however, one would have to demonstrate posi-
tively that the legal philosophies of Holmes and Pound were fundamentally
different from the legal philosophies of Moore or Oliphant, and this in turn
would require a more substantial discussion of the ethical and epistemo-
logical bases of American legal theory than Summers attempts.
Such a demonstration would be a difficult task indeed. It seems obvious
that a behaviourist explanation of the judicial process is completely com-
patible with Holmes’ prediction theory. Both views understand lawyering
as the prediction of the imposition of state sanctions. Both views are com-
pletely result-oriented. Both views maintain a rigid distinction between law
and morality, and both views subscribe to a relativistic ethical theory. The
only apparent difference is that Holmes might have excluded from his “data
base” information about such matters as what a judge had for lunch, or the
predisposition of a decision-maker towards Ukrainian defendants. 63 But he
61Summers, supra, note 1, 42.
62Moore, supra, note 20, 612.
63Indeed, the identification of Holmes with the radical fringe was made in the early 1940s
by the antagonists of realism. It was Holmes, more often than not, who was chosen as the
archetypal realist, usually by virtue of his extreme positivism. See Lucey, supra, note 50.
Pound presents a more delicate challenge, for in many respects his philosophy of law con-
tained substantial elements of natural-law theory. Indeed, there was a fundamental inconsis-
tency between his natural-law inclinations and his subscription to pragmatic explanations in
law. This dialectic in Pound’s thought has been noted and discussed by others. See e.g., Hunt,
supra, note 12, 25-9.
1984]
BOOK REVIEWS
could not have given a convincing reason for so doing if all he cared about
as a lawyer was predicting the imposition of state sanctions. Only the ac-
curacy of the technique chosen to make such predictions could count as a
point of differentiation, and that would be a matter for the quantitative
methods of a statistical science only.
My quarrel with Summers on these points is not over the identification
of basic similarities in thought among the group of American lawyers which
he has chosen at his “classical” pragmatic instrumentalists. There is nothing
remarkable or, it should be added, even new about his observations in this
regard.64 I object instead to his somewhat veiled attempt to resuscitate and
rehabilitate American legal realism by calling it pragmatic instrumentalism
and by excising what he arbitrarily has chosen as its excesses. Any differences
in that legal philosophy’s various manifestations in American legal culture
were, and still are, merely matters of degree and emphasis. Summers is
correct to have noticed that sociological jurisprudence and legal realism
share a pragmatic and utilitarian philosophical orientation. He is mistaken,
however, in his assertion that the value skepticism and behaviouristic sci-
ence of the radical realists were not features inherent in this orientation.
The only difference between a Holmes or a Pound and a Moore or an
Oliphant is that the latter pursued the logic of their pragmatism and utili-
tarianism to its limits. Any attempt to resuscitate realism must take that
extreme view more seriously than merely dismissing it as an aberration. If
Summers finds that view unpalatable, as appears to be the case, then it is
incumbent upon him to articulate more precisely how he distinguishes his
theory from it. The reason he has not done so, I suggest, is that it cannot
be done.
In the third and fourth parts of his book, in which Summers develops
a more elaborate instrumentalist theory, similar errors manifest themselves
more seriously as a fundamental failure to take the utilitarian positivism
of instrumentalist theories seriously. The chief identifying feature of all
instrumentalist theories is that, in positing a means/end dichotomy in law,
they ask their readers to accept the is/ought distinction of positivism and,
64Morton White has identified the philosophical basis shared by several strands of American
thought. See, for example, White, Pragmatism and the American Mind (1973) 41:
Historians of American thought and critics of American culture are only too aware
of the kinship among some of our distinctive intellectual currents –
instrumen-
talism in philosophy, institutionalism in economics, legal realism in the law, eco-
nomic determinism in politics and literature, the new history. From a methodological
as well as a political and ethical point of view they unite to form the distinctive
liberal Weltanschauung of twentieth-century America. No great research is necessary
in order to establish the surface connections of these influential patterns of social
thinking in their mature forms….
REVUE DE DROIT DE McGILL
[Vol. 29
at least, in Summers’ and America’s version, the additional but comple-
mentary utilitarian assumption that law is ideologically and politically neu-
tral.65 Summers’ erection of elaborate analytical schemes describing the
“technique element” of law is fraught with grave danger, precisely because
it requires acceptance of these utilitarian and positivist assumptions about
law.
There cannot be anything inherently objectionable about distinguishing
the law that is from the law that ought to be. Such a categorization is only
a provisional statement until it is informed by some purpose in application
or until it is permitted, in error, to take on a life of its own. It may be
advantageous, for example, to make such distinctions in order to observe
(with Bentham) that what is the law, ought to be reformed, or (with Aquinas)
that what is reputed to be law is not law because it is not an ordinance of
reason for the common good made by he who has care of the community.
One might want to ask, with Summers’ instrumentalists: given that a par-
ticular social goal is perceived to be desirable, and given that the social goal
can be achieved through “law”, what is the most effective legal apparatus
for such purposes? Or, given that a lawyer has a client who has a particular
purpose and given that the client would like to achieve his purpose within
the letter of the law, what is the most effective legal tool at the disposal of
the lawyer? However, the great danger of modern Anglo-American positiv-
ism, instrumental or analytical, is that in its exuberance to identify and
describe the law that is, it usually loses track of its purpose and assumptions
in so doing. Its apparent passion for an autonomous value-neutral science
of social ordering becomes an all-consuming end in itself. It forgets that it
has assumed away many of the most difficult questions about law. As a
consequence, its knowledge is not only an illusion, it is a dangerous illusion,
because by virtue of it law becomes an empty shell capable of undefined
use and manipulation –
the plaything of analytical jurists, the tool of client-
directed lawyers, the “holy grail” of formalists, the object of obedience in
its letter only, a vehicle for the advancement of academic careers, the means
to a comfortable suburban existence, in short, in Leo Strauss’ phrase, the
“handmaid of any powers or any interests that be”.66 As with all positivist
theories, it cannot maintain the integrity of law as a normative system
because it does not claim the force of moral imperatives. 67 Hence, although
one can sympathize with the need to ask instrumentalist-type questions
about law, one wonders about the inherent dangers of an instrumentalist
650n the classification of realism as a positivist theory of law, see Lyons, supra, note 8; W.
Friedmann, Legal Theory, 51h ed. (1967) 292 et seq. and L. Fuller, Law in Quest ofltself(1 940).
66L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (1953) 4.
67See Fuller, supra, note 34.
1984]
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
or any other positivist posture. This is a danger of which Summers appears
entirely unaware.
The author’s apparent insensitivity to this problem is the most curious
feature of the book. Much of the inspiration for Summers’ criticism of
pragmatic instrumentalist thought in America comes from the work of Lon
Fuller who, in a particularly thoughtful essay68 cited several times by Sum-
mers, developed the parallel between the means/end and is/ought dicho-
tomies. Fuller’s observations amount to a denial of the utility of a bald
distinction between means and ends, and effectively demonstrate the es-
sentially positivist basis of much of this reasoning. In several passages in
his book, Summers also recognizes that his pragmatic instrumentalists were
in error in their exclusive concentration on “means” in law. Yet paradox-
ically, in parts three and four of his book, Summers’ principal thesis is that
instrumental theorizing in law is in itself a useful occupation. Indeed, this
portion of the work is wholly consumed by a detailed elaboration of the
law’s “instrumentality”.
The same kind of confusion occurs in Summers’ discussion of the eth-
ical theory underlying the thought of his pragmatic instrumentalists. He
criticizes the ethical relativism of Moore and Oliphant by appealing to ab-
solute values. Yet, as pointed out above, Summers is often relativistic in
his ethical arguments himself. Ironically, Summers’ pragmatic instrumen-
talism is vulnerable to the same criticism that has befallen the thought of
Roscoe Pound in recent years. In the words of one contemporary scholar:
[A] rather less charitable view justifies the conclusion that Pound was unable
to advance a consistent ethical theory. In recognizing the deficiencies of both
the pragmatic and the idealistic theory, he tried to solve his dilemma by com-
bining the two, and in so doing, produces an inevitable and irresolvable con-
tradiction. This contradiction is a manifestation of the deeper conflict between
the two strands of thought, the utilitarian and the idealistic upon the unstable
fusion of which he seeks to construct the edifice of sociological jurisprudence;
as a consequence, this very edifice itself is inherently unstable. 69
So, I think, with Summers’ pragmatic instrumentalism. At one and the
same time, Summers extols the virtues of a thoroughly positivist and eth-
ically relativist theory of law and embraces a natural law and ethically
absolutist criticism of the “radical” aspects of legal relativism.
68Fuller, supra, note 34, infine.
69Hunt, supra, note 12, 28.
Michael Walzer. Spheres of Justice[:] A Defense of Pluralism and Equality.
New York: Basic Books, 1983. Pp. xviii, 345 [$19.951. Reviewed by David
Howes.*
The nature of tyranny is to desire power over the whole world and outside its
own sphere.
Pascal, Pensees
To conceive of “justice” in other than absolute terms would no doubt
strike most legal philosophers and human rights advocates as heretical. In
Spheres of Justice, however, Professor Michael Walzer presents us with an
account of distributive justice which is as relative as it is conducive to the
establishment and maintenance of a just society. In order to appreciate the
full significance of Walzer’s overthrow of absolutist theories of justice (dis-
cussed below) it is necessary to begin by exploring the genealogy of another
concept which has exercised a certain tyranny over contemporary Western
thought, the concept of “the individual”.
The most basic category of modern Western legal and political thought
is that of “the individual”. Prior to the eighteenth century, however, the
concept of “the individual” as we understand it and the related notion of
“equality” (as meaning anything other than equivalence of rank) were un-
thinkable. A group of people was not “made up” of individuals during the
Middle Ages and the Renaissance because the movement of thought was
not from the parts to the whole, but from the whole to its constituent parts.
This reflects the original meaning of the term “individual”, an adjective
(not a substantive), which comes from the Latin individere or “indivisible”.’
The concept of “the individual” represents the starting point of thought
for the modern mind, whereas it used to constitute an endpoint. The social
transformation which precipitated this inversion in the meaning of the term
was the long drawn-out transition from feudalism to capitalism, or as Maine
would have it, “from status to contract”. 2 The feudal social order was un-
dermined by the practise of the idea of ‘the individual’ person as having
universal value, as being a complete manifestation of the essence of man
*B.A. (Trins.), M.Litt. (Oxon.), of the Department of Sociology and Anthropology, Concordia
University and graduating student of the Faculty of Law, McGill University.
‘R. Williams, Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society (1976) 133-6.
2Sir H. Maine, Ancient Law (1917) 100.
McGill Law Journal 1984
Revue de droit de McGill
19841
BOOK REVIEWS
or as embodying, so to speak, humanity in one biological individuum”.3
Society thus became a vacuum since a man’s position within it was no
longer determined by his birth into a particular rank or order. In order to
fill the vacuum a new set of desires, a new psychology, had to be created.
Its architects were Hobbes and Locke. The central axiom of this new psy-
chology (which is also that of economics) was the idea of maximization.
Not only are human wants unlimited, but we constantly strive to maximize
our satisfactions, or so it was and has come to be believed. 4 As a result of
this transformation in attitudes the market came to be seen as the context,
and contract as the medium, through which satisfactions were to be max-
imized. It is little wonder that it was at this historical juncture that the
creation myth of liberal democratic society, Social Contract theory, first
took shape.
According to Locke’s version of Social Contract theory, our ancestors
agreed to quit the state of nature and enter civil society for the mutual
preservation of their property. This myth misrepresents reality, however,
since experience has shown that the market was never designed to “pre-
serve” property in the hands of the many, but to concentrate property (that
is, capital and all of the other goods which it entrains) in the hands of the
few.
There are those, the “Entitlement theorists”, who see nothing wrong
with this result. The fact that the market produces and reproduces ine-
qualities in the distribution of goods is fair, providing the appropriations
(initial acquisitions and subsequent transfers) are just.5 This approach ev-
idently values liberty over equality and accords with the psychology of
Hobbes and Locke.
But the new psychology can be invoked to arrive at the opposite con-
clusion as well. According to such “Rational Choice theorists” as John
Rawls, 6 there are two principles which free and rational individuals placed
in the “original position” of our ancestors, each concerned to maximize his
own satisfactions, would accept as defining the terms of their association
providing that the choice of principles were made behind a “veil of igno-
rance”. The “veil of ignorance” is there to ensure fairness since (Rawls
assumes) if the co-contractors were cognizant of their class position in the
society to come, or the distribution of such personal qualities as intelligence
and strength, Rawls believes each would design principles to favour his
3Dumont, “The Individual” in Two Types of Society (1965) 8 Contributions to Indian So-
ciology 7, 9.
4C.B. Macpherson, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke (1962).
5R. Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (1974).
6J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1971).
REVUE DE DROIT DE McGILL
[Vol. 29
particular condition. The principles are, first, that each individual be allowed
the most extensive liberty compatible with a like liberty for all, and second,
that inequalities in the distribution of goods are permissible if and only if
they make the worst-off people better off than they would be in the absence
of any inequalities.
Both of the above theories arise out of the attempt to discover a single
distributive criterion (free exchange in the first case and limited trade-offs
in the second) capable of ordering the allocation of every conceivable social
good. Both theories also take the “universalism of the individual” (the
individual as embodying humanity) as their point of departure. Neither
theory can derive any support from the disciplines of anthropology or his-
tory, and for these three reasons, I would argue, we ought to discard them.
To begin with, there can be no “original position” outside society, not
even a hypothetical one, because the concept of “the individual”, as we
have seen, is historically and socially determined. Secondly, we are not just
brought together by society to distribute goods among ourselves; first we
have to make them and in making them we imbue them with meanings
which determine their distribution. Rational Choice theorists confine their
attention to distributive acts (sharing, dividing, exchanging) and thereby
miss the fact that we distinguish ourselves from each other by conceiving
and creating, and then possessing and employing goods, in different ways.
The distributive act is but one aspect of a process which is cyclical, the
process of producing and reproducing those goods which have value for us
because they embody a shared understanding of the order of things. Hence,
the Rational Choice theorist asks the wrong question when he inquires:
“What would rational individuals choose under the abstract, universal con-
ditions of the ‘original position’?” Goods and persons are given in history,
that is, under particular conditions. Therefore, the real question sounds
more like: “What choices have we already made in the course of our com-
mon life? What understandings do we (really) share?” Individual choices
only make sense when viewed against the backdrop of collective under-
standings and commitments.
Walzer’s Spheres of Justice is an informally written and highly thought-
provoking attempt to answer the “real question” underlying the distributive
justice debate. The book does not put forward “A Theory of Justice”, but
many, each appropriate to a particular sphere of goods. The distributive
spheres which Walzer discriminates include: money and commodities, se-
curity and welfare, membership, education, recognition, office, work, leisure,
kinship and love, divine grace and, underlying all of the above, political
power.
1984]
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
Walzer breaks with tradition by taking these goods and their meanings,
as opposed to the (putative) nature of the individual, as his point of de-
parture. Rather than multiplying rights indiscriminately in the name of
“equality”, Walzer refreshingly attempts to sort out the logic according to
which we classify goods as belonging to different spheres. His argument is
that a complex equality of persons can be achieved by respecting the au-
tonomy of the spheres.
This sort of inquiry into classificatory boundaries has much to com-
mend it. To take a homely example, earth in the garden is just earth, but
when it gets tracked into the kitchen on our boots it becomes “dirt”. Dirt,
then, as Lord Chesterfield once remarked, is “matter out of place”, or matter
outside its proper sphere. Probing more deeply we find that, “[flor us dirt
is a kind of compendium category for all events which blur, smudge, con-
tradict, or otherwise confuse accepted classifications. The underlying feeling
is that a system of values which is habitually expressed in a given arrange-
ment of things has been violated”. 7
Transgressions are like dirt to us: they trigger the same reaction. For
example, the buying or selling of ecclesiastical office was regarded as a sin
by medieval Christians, the sin of simony. This illustrates what Walzer
would call a “blocked exchange”, or “illegitimate conversion”. Officeholders
were to be chosen for their knowlege and piety, not their wealth. Money
could no more be converted into office than piety could be invoked to
advantage in the marketplace. The pious/impious distinction was a relevant
distributive criterion within the sphere of office but not the sphere of money
and commodities (the market), which was open to everyone. Simony con-
stituted a transgression of boundaries, an intrusion from another sphere.
Walzer makes much of the aphorism, “There are some things that money
can’t buy”, and the book as a whole may be read as an attack on the contrary
maxim, “Everything has its price”. The latter phrase reveals the hegemony
of the market. The sphere of money and commodities repeatedly threatens
to engulf the other spheres because money is the closest thing we have to
a universal medium of exchange. But money is a social good like any other;
there are boundaries to its distribution, and no other sphere illustrates the
limits of commodity fetishism more clearly than that of security and welfare.
Walzer discusses the case of medical care in this connection. During
the Middle Ages, “the cure of souls was public, the cure of bodies private,”8
meaning that doctors tended to cater to the rich. It is apparent to us now
that “care should be proportionate to illness and not to wealth”, 9 but not
7M. Douglas, Implicit Meanings: Essays in Anthropology (1975) 51.
8M. Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (1983) 87.
9 lbid., 86.
McGILL LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 29
so then, since eternity, not longevity, was the socially recognized need. To
ensure that every Christian had an equal chance at salvation and eternal
life, every effort was made to put a church in every parish, whereas now
we find a clinic or hospital in every district. The case of medical care il-
lustrates how in response to a shift in “shared understandings” a commodity
(medical care) was excised from the market, one distributive principle (free
exchange) was replaced by another (need), and as in post-war Britain, doctors
who were professionals and entrepreneurs one year became professionals
and public servants the next.’0
The process described above may be defined as the rectification of
boundaries. Distributive criteria change in accordance with how our con-
ceptions of particular goods transform themselves, but the principle remains
that “different outcomes for different people in different spheres make a just
society”. ” We do not have to be the same in order to be equal since it is
appropriate for inequalities (that is, differences) to exist within each sphere,
but not across them, given our pluralist conception of goods. It is in this
respect that Walzer differs from the Entitlement theorists who generalize or
“universalize” the principle of free exchange and conceive of the subject,
“the individual”, as retaining his or her unity across the spheres. But under
such conditions of complex equality as are latent in the structure of our
beliefs and institutions, the category of “the individual” disintegrates (in
practice). Persons are defined in different terms according to the sphere in
which they operate. In fact, there is injustice wherever a person’s position
in one sphere is reiterated across the others. The position of women is a
case in point. Historically, women were denied the right to vote, hold office,
own property, etc., because it was understood (at least by men) that “A
woman’s place is in the home”. As Walzer observes, this meant that “kinship
patterns [were] dominant outside their sphere. And liberation [began] out-
side, with a succession of claims that this or that social good should be
distributed for its own, not for familial, reasons” (political power and office
by arguing and voting, wealth by bearing risks, recognition by “doing one’s
job”, etc.).’ 2
I think that Walzer’s account ofjustice as inhering in differences enables
us to explain why the current debate on human rights has arrived at an
impasse and seems so sterile. It would appear, as Ian Hunter recently stated,
that:
The continuing pursuit of equality exacts a price in human liberty …
Free-
dom to contract with whom one chooses, freedom to dispose of property,
‘0The current debate over “user fees” is in reality a boundary dispute: “user fees” represent
an intrusion from another sphere.
I’Supra, note 8, 320.
12Supra, note 8, 240.
1984]
BOOK REVIEWS
freedom of choice over one’s tenants and employees –
all such decisions have
been subordinated to an over-arching public policy of equality [enforced by
Human Rights Commissions].13
But the opposition between liberty and equality, which is also the opposition
between Entitlement and Rational Choice theory, is a false one. All inter-
personal relations are mediated by social goods: there is no direct, “im-
mediate” experience of the other Therefore, to argue that this or that freedom
or this or that right inheres in each and every individual is to ignore the
crucial sociological fact that it is the dominance (or as Walzer would say,
“convertibility”) of certain goods that must be restricted. If we respect the
autonomy of the spheres, the autonomy of the person will out.
The formula for a just society which Walzer provides us with runs as
follows: “No social good x should be distributed to men and women who
possess some other good y merely because they possess y and without regard
to the meaning of x”.*4 Thus, ‘for example, honour (x) should not be tied
to office (y), but to a person’s performance in that office, because one must
deserve recognition, it is not an entailment of office. Similarly, ownership
of capital (y) should not be convertible into power over persons (x) as well
as things, because there is nothing in entrepreneurial activity which entitles
the entrepreneur to rule over the rest of us without winning our agreement.
It is important to note that Walzer’s formula (unlike Rawls’) is an open-
ended one: it does not predetermine the end-result.
What a larger conception of justice requires is not that citizens rule and are
ruled in turn, but that they rule in one sphere and are ruled in another –
where ‘rule’ means not that they exercise power but that they enjoy a greater
share than other people of whatever good is being distributed.15
There is, however, one result that Walzer aims for above all else, and
that is to give renewed meaning to the third principle articulated in the
banner cry of the French Revolution: “Liberty, equality and fraternity”. In
1789 the concept of “fraternity” had as much force as a moral and legal
injunction as the other two principles (whereas presently it is difficult to
conceive of fraternity as “a right”). Much of Spheres ofJustice is accordingly
devoted to providing sketches of conditions under which fraternity may
flourish. For example, three ways of collecting blood for hospital use –
voluntary donation, purchase and imposing a tax –
are discussed in terms
of which way best “expresses and enhances a spirit of communal altruism”.’ 6
More basically, Walzer is an advocate of decentralized democratic socialism,
patronage on a local scale and economic associations along the lines of the
13Liberty and Equality: A Tale of Tivo Codes (1983) 29 McGill L.J. 1, 5.
‘4Supra, note 8, 20.
‘5Supra, note 8, 321.
16Supra, note 8, 93.
REVUE DE DROIT DE McGILL
[Vol. 29
medieval guild. The worker-controlled factory and the kibbutz are held up
as model institutions wherein not only the work is shared, but decisions
about the work as well. In the final analysis, then, self-respect and citizenly
virtue (in the sense of resisting the dominance of corporate wealth and power
or challenging the insolence of office-holders) amount to the same thing.
Democratic politics, once we have overthrown every wrongful dominance, is
a standing invitation to act in public and know oneself a citizen, capable of
choosing destinations and accepting risks for oneself and others, and capable,
too, of patrolling the distributive boundaries and sustaining a just society.’ 7
It would be naive to criticize Walzer for being a relativist because the
whole point of Spheres of Justice is to show that there are no universal
standards by which to judge an act or a society as just or unjust. Cultures
cannot be ranked in relation to each other. Moreover, there is one point on
which Walzer is very clear and the case of medical care illustrates very well:
“what is at stake is [always] the readiness of the community to live up to
the logic of its own institutions”.’ 8 Once the boundaries have been drawn,
separate and distinct standards of distribution lock into place in each sphere
and there can be no half-measures in, for example, the provision of medical
care. Of course, the boundaries will always be the subject of conflict and
argument, but such disputes are a good thing because they bring our con-
ceptions of the goods at stake into sharper relief.
Walzer is immune from criticism with regard to the standards he ar-
ticulates, but this is not the case with respect to the spheres he discriminates.
Is the list of eleven spheres exhaustive? Can the spheres really be regarded
as equal when it is admitted that “what we do with regard to membership
structures all our other distributive choices: it determines with whom we
make those choices,”‘ 9 etc.? Similarly, political power is not just a good
which men and women pursue, it is also used to defend (or revise) “the
boundaries of all the distributive spheres, including its own, and to enforce
the common understandings of what goods are and what they are for”. 20
This implies the existence of a hierarchy of spheres: membership and politics
are spheres of a higher logical type than the rest. Finally, there is one very
obvious problem with a philosophy ofjustice built up on the shifting sands
of aphorisms: appearances tend to get mistaken for reality.
Many of the most basic concepts in Spheres of Justice call for further
clarification, then, but the book stands as one of the two most important
modem treatises on the subject of distributive justice, the other account
7Supra, note 8, 311.
18Supra, note 8, 85.
19Supra, note 8, 31.
20Supra, note 8, 15.
1984]
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
being Rawls’. 2 1 By breaking the stalemate between Rational Choice and
Entitlement theory, and by displacing our attention from the “universalism
of the individual” to the “pluralism of goods”, Walzer has enabled us to
throw off the monolithic theories of the past and begin to see justice in the
differences that surround us.
2’Supra, note 6.
Barry Nicholas, French Law of Contract. London: Butterworths, 1982. Pp.
xxxviii, 253; Lionel Neville Brown and John Francis Garner, French Ad-
ministrative Law, 3d ed. London: Butterworths, 1983. Pp. xvii, 218; Otto
Kahn-Freund, Claudine Levy and Bernard Rudden, A Source-Book of French
Law, 2d ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979. Pp. xxviii, 550. Re-
viewed by Richard J. Cummins.*
Many lawyers and students think of comparative law as a dull subject
best left to a few scholars of vaguely foreign background. In fact, it is one
of the most exciting areas of the law, combining the need for the best tech-
nical skills with the opportunity to study the broadest and most fundamental
legal issues. It is certainly a field in which there are fewer scholars and less
good writing than there should be. It is a pleasure, therefore, to review three
excellent books dealing with French law which have recently appeared in
England in original or new editions.
Of the books reviewed, only that by Professor Nicholas’ is completely
new, but it seems nevertheless appropriate to look at them together as pre-
senting a coherent body of work permitting access to French law to the
student, practitioner or professor trained primarily in a common law system.
Such books are all too rare and often fail to get the international distribution
that they merit.2
Thus, it is hoped that this review will help these very useful books get
a wider audience outside of England. It also provides a fitting occasion to
reflect on the way the student, practitioner or scholar in one system enters
into contact with other legal systems, and on the kinds of tools that com-
paratists must continue to develop to make that contact yet more fruitful
and effective.
In a brief but perceptive preface to his French Law of Contract, Professor
Nicholas addresses some of these issues. The book is described as an “es-
say”, 3 a word suggesting a more informal, intuitive approach, a lighter bag-
gage than a treatise or other more formal structure would carry. This is
wholly appropriate. Comparative law writing may legitimately be more am-
bitious than to, in Professor Nicholas’ phrase, “enable one to use the index
to a foreign law book”.4 It is, nevertheless, in its approach to the foreign
material more art than science in mediating between one more or less co-
herent intellectual whole and another without being able to achieve the
*General Counsel, Mobil Oil Frangaise.
‘B. Nicholas, French Law of Contract (1982).
2The leading book in the field remains A.T. von Mehren & J.R. Gordley, The Civil Law
3Nicholas, supra, note 1, v.
41bid.
System, 2nd ed. (1977).
@McGill Law Journal 1984
Revue de droit de McGill
1984]
BOOK REVIEWS
purity of structure of either. Anyone who has tried to understand a foreign
language and culture well will doubtless know the experience. Absolutes of
one culture or system seem to be quite relative in another; communication
must be partly in terms of one and partly in terms of the other.
Professor Nicholas’ book naturally reflects this tension. French treatises
do not treat contracts separately from the general law of obligations, as a
discussion starting from English law must do. Even within the law of con-
tracts further conflicts of structure are found. Specific contracts are, for
example, more important in French than in Anglo-American systems. 5 The
treatment of case law is equally delicate. An English lawyer will not learn
much without reference to the cases, but their role in French legal analysis,
although more important than in the past, 6 is difficult to define and easy
to falsify when an author with English analytical habits attempts to treat
French materials.
A writer dealing with such a subject is left with a series of compromises
which are not entirely satisfactory to the fastidious. The value of such a
work is, however, precisely in this mediating function, a task invaluable to
the beginner (who will inevitably get less from working directly with French
books) and very useful at any stage. Without going any further, it must be
said that Professor Nicholas provides, by and large, the most satisfactory
and coherent short treatment of the French law of contracts in a long time.
The book does more than teach elementary French contracts; the in-
troduction is particularly valuable,7 covering as it does the background of
the distinction between common and civil law, the principal characteristics
of French law and the basic divisions used in that system. Although all this
is done in twenty-seven pages nothing essential to the beginning student is
left out.
In dealing with the distinction between common and civil law, Professor
Nicholas quite properly points out that the common lawyer’s perspective,
enabling him easily to perceive the similarity between civil systems, often
leads him to ignore their differences. These are much greater after nine-
teenth-century codification than they were when Roman law was more di-
rectly influential. 8 A page or two on the origins and characteristics of the
principal civil systems might have been of interest here.
The discussion of the characteristics of French law will be useful to all
but the most sophisticated. 9 Although it focuses on contrasts with English
Vlbid., vi.
6See the discussion in J. Ghestin, Traite de Droil Civil (1977) vol.1, 316-62.
7See Nicholas, supra, note 1, 1-27.
8lbid., 5.
91bid., 4-22.
REVUE DE DROIT DE McGILL
[Vol. 29
practice, American and Canadian lawyers will not be hindered. In fact, the
codifying approach to legislation in their countries is perhaps more like
French than English practice. The court system is described well, and the
problem of defining the French approach to case law is tackled admirably.
In the brief space allotted to this fascinating and difficult subject, Professor
Nicholas shows how the need of any modem judicial system to fill in the
gaps in the codes and legislation conflicts with the prohibition in the Code
Civil against making “pronouncements of a general and normative kind”. ‘ 0
Case law is often followed in practice, but the principle that it is not a source
of law but only an authority in fact leads in his view to a system where
results may be less predictable. This is a fruitful area for research, as attitudes
in France have evolved considerably in the direction of a greater role for
case law,” I and it is to be hoped that some aspiring doctoral candidate will
make a thorough study of this subject.
The presentation of the divisions of French law which Professor Ni-
cholas treats next is, necessarily, very brief. The difficult subject of the
definition of administrative contracts is, for example, not easy to treat in a
few pages.’ 2
The discussion of contract law which makes up the rest of the book is
admirably succinct, neatly blending French categories with English divisions
(e.g. “Remedies for non-performance”). A common lawyer will find this
discussion indispensible. Everywhere it is illustrated by French and English
cases. It would perhaps have been of interest to include some cases from
common law jurisdictions other than England, in addition to the few ref-
erences to the American Uniform Commercial Code.
Professor Nicholas’ book contains certain practical aids for the beginner
which will make it a good textbook, including a note on sources and lit-
erature which provides orientation for the beginner looking for books to
buy. 13 The reference to the new treatise directed by Professor Ghestin, of
which three volumes have appeared, is particularly welcome.
In the text of the Nicholas book, frequent reference is made to A Source-
Book of French Law14 by the late Professor Otto Kahn-Freund, Miss Clau-
dine Levy and Professor Bernard Rudden, which is in fact a most useful
companion to French Law of Contract. Although like the Nicholas work it
will be most helpful to the beginner, even the mature scholar will find it
“Code Civil, art. 5; Nicholas, supra, note 1, 12-8.
“See, for example, the discussion in Ghestin, supra, note 6.
‘2The discussion of this issue in G. Vedel, Droit administratif, 71h ed. (1980) covers 50 pages.
“3Nicholas, supra, note 1, xxxiii-xxxv.
140, Kahn-Freund, C. Ievy & B. Rudden, A Source-book on French Law, 2nd ed. (1982)
[hereinafter Kahn-Freund].
1984]
CHRONIQUE BIBLIOGRAPHIQUE
useful for its clear organization and wealth of material. In the words of the
preface by Professor Andr6 Tunc, “it gives an excellent view of the sources,
categories and institutions of French law”. 15 A collection of readings in
French, with ample introductory material and commentary in English, it
parallels the Nicholas book in providing both a general introduction to
French law and institutions and the elements of the law of contract, but is
both wider in scope and fuller in content.
Produced principally for use by undergraduate students at Oxford be-
ginning French law after having studied their own system, its preparation
required careful consideration of the goals of such comparative study and
the most effective way of entering into it. As Professor Rudden states in the
introduction, comparative law is “not a subject at all but — as its French
a method, a discipline”.’ 6 The approach chosen re-
name makes clear –
quired attacking the hard subjects directly, those areas which are, or seem
to be, strange and different, and placing strong emphasis on sources and
methods.
The section on sources and methods admirably sets the French legal
system in its appropriate constitutional context by starting with a large
extract from the Constitution of 1958 and doctrinal material relating to it.
Constitutions have often been less important in France than in some other
countries, but the increasingly active role of the Conseil Constitutionnel has
changed all that and the emphasis is entirely appropriate. Sections on the
function of a code, interpretation of statutes and contracts, the method of
using case law and doctrine follow. Each has a selection of readings from
statutes, regulations, cases and particularly doctrine, accompanied by helpful
clarifying notes and questions which will provoke thought and aid analysis.
While the introduction to the Nicholas book is quite brief, the sources
and methods section of the Source-book makes up fully two-thirds of that
text. It provides a full introduction to the principal issues for a student who
will only take one course or a lawyer who has to be satisfied with a basic
acquaintance with the issues, and furnishes the background necessary for
further study of the great French treatises, Mazeaud,17 Carbonnier’8 or
Ghestin.19
The well-organized section on contracts provides a fitting companion
for the Nicholas book. Professor Rudden is probably right in saying that
the law of contracts provides the best material, for an introductory course
’51bid., xii.
’61bid., 1.
17H., L. & J. Mazeaud, Leqons de droit civil, 7th ed. (1983).
18J. Carbonnier, Droit civil, 14th ed. (1982).
19Ghestin, supra, note 6.
McGILL LAW JOURNAL
[Vol. 29
in comparative law, 20 although it would be interesting to see how a book
dealing on the same scale with tort or property law, or even a modern subject
like competition law, would look.
As a basic grounding in French law should surely include some intro-
duction to public as well as private law, Brown and Gamer’s French Ad-
ministrative Law2′ will be very useful. Based originally on lectures given
by each of the authors at their respective universities, it retains some of the
marks of the lecture form, making a certain amount of repetition and a
somewhat looser organization inevitable. It is nevertheless rich in material
and covers the elements of the subject quite thoroughly.
While comparative studies in private law are primarily justified as in-
creasing access to another system because that knowledge is or may be useful,
and only secondarily for the light they may shed on one’s own system, public
law and especially administrative law are principally of interest in helping
us to understand the functioning of our own system.
In their introduction, the authors therefore rightly emphasize that the
comparative method “is of particular importance in administrative law,
because … the question of how government can be controlled in the in-
terests of both state and citizen, [is] common to all the developed nations
of the Western World”. 22 In addition, French administrative law has char-
acteristics which make it an interesting subject of comparative study as a
civil law system. 23 Unlike French private law it is uncodified, and unlike
administrative legal systems in common law jurisdictions, which share both
substantive law and courts with the private law, it is a fully developed
independent system with its own courts.
An introductory chapter considers the constitutional and administra-
tive background. 24 After outlining briefly the expanded role of reglementary
power (pouvoir rglementaire) as opposed to legislative power (pouvoir l-
gislati/) under the Constitution of 1958, the authors deal with the Conseil
Constitutionnel and describe its growing power and confidence before turn-
ing to administrative law proper. Basic notions of local government whose
activities are, of course, the principal source of administrative cases are also
covered.
Two long chapters deal with the administrative courts and their pro-
cedures, and especially with the organization, history and operation of what
20Kahn-Freund, supra, note 14, 3.
21 L.N. Brown & J.F Garner, French Administrative Law, 3rd ed. (1983).
22Ibid., 1.
231bid., 2.
24Ibid., 6-26.
1984]
BOOK REVIEWS
the authors rightly regard as one of the most fascinating of French insti-
tutions, the chief administrative court, the Conseil d’Etat.25 Composed of
some of the best members of the civil service, it exercises extensive legis-
lative as well as judicial functions. The former include examining the text
of all proposed legislation and regulations, and the relative readability and
clarity of French legislation and regulations are- no doubt to some extent
due to prior examination by this expert body.
The judicial function of this institution is perhaps of greater interest to
students. The process of examination of cases by the Conseil d’Etat is pain-
staking and thorough.26 Although it would be hard to say that the Conseil
d’Etat has the same public recognition in France as has, for example, the
Supreme Court in the United States, its great prestige within the adminis-
tration and the ruling class generally is a strong guarantee of independence:
it has several times succeeded in exercising its influence during severe po-
litical crises without endangering its role.27
Two chapters deal with jurisdiction, dividing the subject into parts
roughly approximating subject matter jurisdiction and standing in American
constitutional law. In the first area, the authors deal judiciously with the
very difficult issues involved in grappling with notions like “public service”
or “public authority” (puissance publique) as the way to define administra-
tive subject matter jurisdiction. 28 A further two chapters deal with matters
of substantive law, treating administrative liability and problems concerned
with the legality of decisions of the administration.
A chapter on the influence of French administrative law outside France
(including a consideration of its effect on the Court of Justice of the European
Communities) and one evaluating the system’s merits and defects close the
book. The authors, great admirers of the French system, are very convincing
in arguing its merits.
Books like these set a very high standard. It is to be hoped they point
toward a revival and expansion of comparative studies.
2SIbid., 41-77.
26Ibid., 58-69.
271bid., 31.
28 Ibid., 79-83.