Original Facts: Skill, Judgment,
and the Public Domain
Teresa Scassa*
It has long been said that facts cannot be protected
by copyright. Copyright jurisprudence has been less
than clear, however, about what constitutes a fact, and
about the reasons why facts cannot be copyrighted. The
Supreme Court of Canada, in its recent decision in
CCH Canadian Ltd. v. Law Society of Upper Canada,
restated the principle that facts cannot be copyrighted.
At the same time, the Court set a standard for
originality that can easily be interpreted so as to offer
copyright protection to facts.
In this paper, the author explores the concept of
facts and the way in which Canadas standard for
originality might be used to extend copyright to facts.
She focuses on the problems that face courts in cases
involving original factsthose facts that owe their
existence to the exercise of individual intellectual
effort. She identifies and discusses three kinds of
original facts: those discovered through skill and
judgment, those that are valuable due to the particular
selection or arrangement, and those that are not
necessarily
is
compared with American and Australian cases,
revealing different ways of applying the principle that
there is no copyright in facts. The author examines the
policy reasons why facts should not be copyrightable,
and argues for an interpretive approach that leaves facts
in the public domain.
true. Jurisprudence
from Canada
Il a t longtemps affirm que les faits ne
pouvaient pas tre protgs par le droit dauteur. La
jurisprudence dans le domaine du droit dauteur est
cependant loin dtre prcise sur ce qui est de savoir ce
que constitue un fait et sur les raisons pour lesquelles
les faits ne sauraient tre protgs par le droit dauteur.
Dans un rcent arrt, CCH Canadian Ltd. v. Law
Society of Upper Canada, la Cour Suprme du Canada
a ritr le principe selon lequel les faits ne pouvaient
tre protgs par le droit dauteur. Toutefois la Cour a
dvelopp une condition doriginalit qui pourrait
facilement permettre, par une interprtation extensive,
une protection des faits par la loi sur le droit dauteur.
Dans cet article, lauteur examine la notion de
faits et la manire dont il est possible dinterprter le
critre doriginalit au Canada pour tendre aux faits la
protection offerte par le droit dauteur. Lauteur se
penche particulirement sur les problmes auxquels les
tribunaux sont confronts dans les cas portant sur des
faits originaux; faits qui doivent leurs existences un
effort de nature individuel et intellectuel. Lauteur
identifie et met en lumire trois types de faits
originaux : ceux qui sont les produits du talent et du
jugement, ceux qui ont acquis de la valeur la suite
dun effort de slection ou darrangement et ceux qui ne
sont pas ncessairement vrais. La
jurisprudence
canadienne est ensuite compare la jurisprudence des
tats-Unis et celle de lAustralie afin de mettre en
vidence les diffrentes manires dont le principe selon
lequel les faits ne sauraient bnficier de la protection
du droit dauteur est appliqu. Lauteur examine
galement les raisons politiques avances pour fonder
la proposition selon laquelle les faits ne devraient pas
tre protge par le droit dauteur et milite pour une
approche interprtative qui prconise le maintien des
faits dans le domaine public.
* Associate Professor, Dalhousie Law School, Director, Law and Technology Institute. This paper
was first presented at the Intellectual Property Scholars Workshop, University of Western Ontario, 20-
22 January 2005.
Teresa Scassa 2006
To be cited as: (2006) 51 McGill L.J. 253
Mode de rfrence : (2006) 51 R.D. McGill 253
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
[Vol. 51
254
Introduction
255
257
260
263
264
265
267
269
272
274
276
277
I. The Originality Threshold
II. Original Facts
III. An Attempt to Define Facts
A. Information That Is Knowable Only Through the
Exercise of Considerable Skill and Judgment
B. Information That Is Useful or Valuable Only
Because of the Way in Which It Has Been Selected
or Arranged
C. Information That Is Not Necessarily True
IV. Copyright and Facts
A. United States
B. Canada
C. Facts and the Public Domain
Conclusion
2006]
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
255
Introduction
The recent decision of the Supreme Court of Canada in CCH Canadian Ltd. v.
Law Society of Upper Canada1 has, in theory at least, put to rest the debate in
Canadian copyright law over the appropriate standard of originality.2 The unanimous
Court defined originality as requiring an exercise of skill and judgment on the part
of the author of the work. They explicitly rejected labour alone as a basis for
copyright protection, and rejected the higher standard of creativity. In elaborating
on the standard of skill and judgment, Chief Justice McLachlin stated that the
exercise of skill and judgment required to produce the work must not be so trivial
that it could be characterized as a purely mechanical exercise.3
In the cases that will follow, courts will address the important question of
originality, and more specifically consider how to maintain a distinction in the
analysis between the application of the standard for originality to the work itself to
determine if copyright subsists, and the extent of any infringement of copyright. In
other words, as Ginsburg stated in her article on copyright in informational works,
the difficult pragmatic question becomes the appropriate scope of protection.4 A
compilation of facts may be original as a result of a selection or arrangement of
facts involving skill and judgment. Determining the scope of protection for selections
or arrangements of facts remains a thorny problem. It is also an issue that bears
directly upon the scope of the public domain in Canada.
In an earlier comment on the CCH Canadian decision,5 I argue that the skill and
judgment standard for originality is not, in practical terms, much different from the
US Supreme Courts modicum of creativity threshold established in Feist
1 [2004] 1 S.C.R. 339, 236 D.L.R. (4th) 395, 2004 SCC 13 [CCH Canadian cited to S.C.R.].
2 The Copyright Act (R.S.C. 1985, c. C-42 [Copyright Act]) states that copyright subsists in every
original literary, dramatic, musical and artistic work (ibid., s. 5(1) [emphasis added]). Prior to CCH
Canadian, two camps were in battle over the meaning of the term. On one side were those who argued
that originality required nothing more than labour: a work was original if its author had invested
labour in its creation. The other side argued for a slightly higher threshold, one that had the work
originating from the author through some kind of authorial, if not creative, act. Although the Federal
Court of Appeal had already rejected sweat of the brow as the standard of originality in Canada
(Tele-Direct (Publications) Inc. v. American Business Information Inc. (1997), [1998] 2 F.C. 22, 154
D.L.R. (4th) 328 (C.A.) [Tele-Direct cited to F.C.], affg (1996) 113 F.T.R. 123, 74 C.P.R. (3d) 72
(F.C.T.D.), leave to appeal to S.C.C. refused, [1998] 1 S.C.R. xv), vigorous argument was made before
the Supreme Court of Canada that sweat of the brow should be the accepted standard of originality.
3 CCH Canadian, supra note 1 at para. 25.
4 Jane C. Ginsburg, Creation and Commercial Value: Copyright Protection of Works of
Information (1990) 90 Colum. L. Rev. 1865 at 1870 [emphasis in original].
5 Teresa Scassa, Recalibrating Copyright Law?: A Comment on the Supreme Court of Canadas
Decision in CCH Canadian Limited et al. v. Law Society of Upper Canada (2004) 3 C.J.L.T. 89. A
similar argument is made by Professor Daniel Gervais in Canadian Copyright Law Post-CCH
(2005) 18 I.P.J. 131 at 139ff.
[Vol. 51
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
256
Publications Inc. v. Rural Telephone Service Co. Inc.6 Both thresholds require some
intellectual contribution (however modest) to the creation of the work. But the choice
by the Supreme Court of Canada to extract language from the sweat of the brow
line of cases in setting the standard for originality sends an ambiguous message. In
addition, unlike the US Supreme Court, the Canadian Court does not take any
particular pains to emphasize the difference between the analysis required to
determine if there is sufficient originality for copyright to subsist, and the ensuing
analysis of the scope of copyright.7 While the Canadian Supreme Court accepts that
facts are not the subject matter of copyright, the concept of fact is given no
elaboration, and little direct attention is given to issues of the scope of copyright in
fact-based works.
In this paper, I will argue that the skill and judgment standard formulated by
the Court must be carefully applied so as not to extend copyright protection to what I
call original facts. I will explain this concept in greater detail later in the paper. For
now, it is enough to say that original facts are those that can be said to result from an
exercise of skill and judgment on the part of an individual. The term original facts
recognizes that the concept of a fact is considerably more nuanced than much
copyright case law would allow. I will argue that there is an important reason to
distinguish between the skill and judgment that gives rise to facts and that which
gives rise to a copyright-protected work. In doing so, I will argue that the skill and
judgment standard embraced by the Court in CCH Canadian must be read alongside
its concurrent statement that there is no copyright in facts,8 and the Courts defence of
a vigorous public domain.9
6 499 U.S. 340, 111 S. Ct. 1282 (1991) [Feist cited to U.S.]. Notwithstanding the view of the
Supreme Court of Canada to the contrary, the American and Canadian standards of originality are very
similar in that both require some degree of intellectual effort. Viewed in this light, a modicum of
creativity and an exercise of skill and judgment are not wildly dissimilar.
7 OConnor J., for the unanimous U.S. Supreme Court in Feist, stated that the non-copyrightability
of facts inevitably means that the copyright in a factual compilation is thin (ibid. at 349). The
American approach clearly mandates a two-stage analysis. In the first stage, the court must determine
whether the selection or arrangement of facts is sufficiently original for copyright to subsist. In the
second stage, it must consider whether there has been substantial taking from the selection or
arrangement, as opposed to the underlying facts themselves. In CCH Canadian (supra note 1) this
two-stage analysis is less evident, since once it was determined that there was copyright in the
compilations, the Court found there was infringement because the works were photocopied.
8 McLachlin C.J. writes that in Canada, as in the United States, copyright protection does not
extend to facts or ideas but is limited to the expression of ideas (CCH Canadian Ltd., ibid. at para.
22).
9 The Court refers to the importance of a robust public domain in both Thberge v. Galerie dArt du
Petit Champlain inc., [2002] 2 S.C.R. 336 at para. 32, 210 D.L.R. (4th) 385, 2002 SCC 34 [Thberge
cited to S.C.R.], and CCH Canadian, ibid. at para. 23.
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
I. The Originality Threshold
Copyright legislation recognizes and gives legal status to authorial acts. The
concept of originality is descriptive of the kind of authorial effort that warrants
protection through copyrights significant statutory monopoly. Too low a standard of
originality gives rise to potentially excessive legal protection for works; too high a
standard might accord too little protection to achieve the objectives of copyright
legislation.10 As Chief Justice McLachlin stated in CCH Canadian:
257
When courts adopt a standard of originality requiring only that something be
more than a mere copy or that someone simply show industriousness to ground
copyright in a work, they tip the scale in favour of the authors or creators
rights, at the loss of societys interest in maintaining a robust public domain that
could help foster future creative innovation.11
Defining originality in such a context is not simply a statement about authorship; it is
a ruling on the economic boundaries of various activities.
The relationship between authorship and the economy is a dynamic one.
Copyright is arguably intended to provide an incentive to authors to produce new
works for the benefit of society.12 The kinds and categories of authorship are
presumably not closed, just as the kinds and categories of economic activity evolve
over time. The recent shift towards an information economy has had an impact on the
kinds of works for which copyright protection is sought, and on the way in which
such works are produced. The paradigm of the individual author striving to create an
original work has, in many contexts, been replaced by an investment of capital and
labour to produce works that reflect a collective routine effort to generate a
compilation for a commercial marketplace. As the centrality of the individual author
diminishes, the drive to link the copyright monopoly to the authors substitute
capital and labourincreases. The sweat of the brow threshold for originality in
some copyright jurisdictions reflects a recognition of labour and capital as a stand-in
for the more traditional author.
Significantly, however, sweat of the brow is an older doctrine, having its roots
in nineteenth-century English case law. These early cases still largely recognized
individual authorial effort. The context in which the works at issue were created can
be distinguished from the contemporary context. The role of the individual as an
10 These objectives were described in Thberge as striking a balance between the rights of creators
and the rights of users of copyright works (ibid. at para. 30). They are reiterated in CCH Canadian,
ibid.
11 CCH Canadian, ibid. at para. 23.
12 The historical public policy objectives of copyright law are a matter of some academic debate.
Certainly, it is a widely held view that copyright law serves as an economic incentive for authors and
artists to create works. This view is reflected in the U.S. Constitutions grant of authority to the federal
government to legislate with respect to copyrights [t]o promote the Progress of Science and useful
Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right to their respective
Writings and Discoveries (U.S. Const., art. I, 8, cl. 8).
[Vol. 51
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
258
author of works can change significantly even within the context of particular kinds
of works. For example, where at one time the individual authorial effort might have
been palpable in the creation of a compilation of facts, digital technologies have so
automated the processes for generating certain types of compilations that the authorial
effort in such works is much less evident.13 If authorial effort is a measure of
copyrightability, the fact that some kinds of factual compilations once received
copyright protection does not necessarily mean that they deserve the same protection
today.14
In setting the skill and judgment standard for originality in Canada, the
Supreme Court of Canada apparently sought to filter out purely or even largely
mechanical processes for generating works (most likely compilations) from the realm
of copyright law.15 In doing so, the Court expressly rejected sweat of the brow as
the measure of originality for copyright purposes.16 The mere expenditure of effort is
not qualitatively sufficient to warrant copyright protection. The Court ruled that
works that result from purely mechanical efforts will not acquire copyright protection
because their creation does not reflect skill and judgment. Originality, therefore, is a
qualitative threshold. Some types of effort expended by humans will clearly not
amount to an exercise of skill and judgment.17 Copyright protection will exist only
13 Ginsburg refers to factual compilations as works of low authorship in contrast to more creative
works of high authorship (supra note 4). In the modern context, the labour involved in the creation
of a directory, for example, might be significantly reduced by the possibility of automated data input,
as well as computer software that automatically sorts data according to particular parameters. This
technology may significantly diminish the degree of author-centred effort involved in creating the
work; at the same time, it may also increase the degree of capital investment required to produce such
works.
14 The thread of unfair competition principles run through the early directory cases; there,
copyright infringement was often found in circumstances in which competitors copied materials from
fact-based works. As I argue elsewhere, copyright law has become intertwined, to some disadvantage,
with unfair competition law principles; this intertwining is particularly true for fact-based works. See
Teresa Scassa, Originality and Utilitarian Works: The Uneasy Relationship between Copyright Law
and Unfair Competition (2004) 1 U. Ottawa L. & Tech. J. 51.
15 McLachlin C.J. writes: The exercise of skill and judgment required to produce the work must not
be so trivial that it could be characterized as a purely mechanical exercise (CCH Canadian, supra
note 1 at para. 25).
16 CCH Canadian, ibid. at para. 24. It is interesting that in rejecting sweat of the brow, McLachlin
C.J. writes: The sweat of the brow approach to originality is too low a standard. It shifts the balance
of copyright protection too far in favour of the owners rights, and fails to allow copyright to protect
the publics interest in maximizing the production and dissemination of intellectual works (ibid. at
para. 24). This is a rather odd statement. The problem with fact-based works is that without protection,
there is arguably little incentive to create and disseminate such works. It is not immediately obvious
how largely removing such works from the scope of copyright protection achieves any kind of
balance between the rights of the creators of such works and the broader public interest. Indeed,
Ginsburg argues that while works of low authorship do not fit comfortably within the copyright
paradigm, they are deserving of protection (supra note 4).
17 In CCH Canadian, supra note 1, McLachlin C.J. gave basic editing as an example of work that
failed to meet the necessary threshold of skill and judgment (ibid. at para. 35). This example is a
259
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
where there is a qualitatively sufficient expenditure of authorial effort. Put another
way, it will exist where there is authorial effort, and such effort is defined in terms of
an exercise either in creativity, or in skill and judgment. Rote or mechanical efforts
are not rewarded with a monopoly.
In reaching its decision in CCH Canadian, the Supreme Court of Canada did not
explicitly distinguish between a standard of originality required for compilations of
fact and one required for more general categories of works. Chief Justice McLachlin
seems to suggest, however, that there are two categories of works that can qualify as
original under the Copyright Act. Works resulting from an exercise of skill and
judgment are original, [w]hile creative works will by definition be original and
covered by copyright.18 If the Courts decision can thus be read as separating original
works into two categoriesthose inherently creative and those requiring skill and
judgmentthe Court seems to recognize two levels of authorship.19 The common
thread is some form of intellectual engagement in the process of creating the work.
The opposite of this intellectual engagement would appear to be rote or mechanical
effort.20 The choice of the terms skill and judgment, however, extracted as they are
from sweat of the brow jurisprudence,21 can lead very easily to an overinclusive
standard of originality. The Court claims it is setting a standard at a midpoint between
sweat of the brow and creativity, but given that it engages with very little of the
prior case law or literature in the area, it is difficult to grasp what its version of the
good illustration of the problems inherent in any qualitative measure for originality. See Scassa, supra
note 5.
18 CCH Canadian, ibid. at para. 25.
19 Ginsburg distinguishes between two levels of authorship when she writes:
We have now, as we have long had, two kinds of copyright: in high authorship works,
such as novels and narrative histories, copyright protects the authorial presence within
the work; in low authorship works, such as telephone directories and compilations of
stock quotations, copyright protects the labor and resources invested in the works
creation (supra note 4 at 1870).
Significantly, Ginsburgs article shortly predates the U.S. Supreme Courts decision in Feist and
is even cited by the court in that case. See Feist, supra note 6. Although the court in Feist recognized
the possibility of granting copyright protection to works of low authorship, it also accorded such
works a relatively low level of protection.
20 McLachlin C.J. expressly excludes this type of effort from protection. See CCH Canadian, supra
note 1 at para. 25.
21 Older sweat of the brow cases in Canada referred to skill, judgment or labour or various
constellations of these qualities as setting the standard for originality in Canada. In Ascot Jockey Club
v. Simons (1968), 64 W.W.R. 411, 56 C.P.R. 122 (B.C.S.C.) [Ascot cited to W.W.R.] the court referred
to sufficient labour, knowledge and judgment (ibid. at 422). In U & R Tax Services Ltd. v. H & R
Block Canada Inc. (1995), 97 F.T.R. 259, 62 C.P.R. (3d) 257 (F.C.T.D.) [cited to F.T.R.], Richard J.
referred to labour, skill and judgment (ibid. at para. 24). In British Columbia Jockey Club v. Standen
(1985), 22 D.L.R. (4th) 467, [1985] 6 W.W.R. 683, 8 C.P.R. (3d) 283 (B.C.C.A.) [B.C. Jockey Club
(C.A.) cited to D.L.R.], affg (1983), 146 D.L.R. (3d) 693, [1983] 4 W.W.R. 537, 73 C.P.R. (2d) 164
(B.C.S.C.) [B.C. Jockey Club (S.C.) cited to D.L.R.], the British Columbia Court of Appeal adopted
the standard relied upon by the trial judge that referred to work, skill, judgment and knowledge
(B.C. Jockey Club (S.C.), ibid. at 703-704).
[Vol. 51
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
260
midpoint might be. If what the Court has done is simply remove works produced by
purely mechanical effort from the reach of the standard of originality, then the result
is hardly less inclusive than sweat of the brow. If it is looking for some qualitative
measure of intellectual effort, it is much closer to the American standard, which it
misrepresents as creativity.22 The fact that the Canadian Court finds that basic
editorial work does not meet the standard suggests it is closer to the American
threshold.23
Guidance in the application of the Courts skill and judgment standard must be
sought from other elements in the Courts decision, as well as in other recent cases
decided by the Court. In CCH Canadian, the Court affirms that there is no copyright
in facts. At the same time, it affirms a central role in Canadian copyright law for a
vigorous public domainan approach that is evident in other recent decisions.24 The
standard of originality must therefore be read in conjunction both with the Courts
statement that there is no copyright in facts and a robust understanding of the public
domain.
II. Original Facts
The bar on copyrighting facts may be reconcilable with a standard of originality
that requires some minimal level of creativity.25 It is less clear that it can exist
comfortably alongside a skill and judgment standard of originality. The difference
between the two standards is at some level semantic. Yet in law, the choice of words
22 OConnor J. in Feist, referred to a minimal level of creativity (supra note 6 at 358 [emphasis
added]). In rejecting what she terms the creativity standard from Feist, McLachlin C.J. wrote: A
creativity standard implies that something must be novel or non-obviousconcepts more properly
associated with patent law than copyright law (CCH Canadian, supra note 1 at para. 24). Yet
OConnor J., in Feist, specifically states that novelty is not required by the standard for originality
(ibid.).
23 For example, McLachlin C.J., in referring to the editors review of decisions for minor
grammatical errors and spelling mistakes states: Any skill and judgment that might be involved in
making these minor changes and additions to the judicial reasons are too trivial to warrant copyright
protection (CCH Canadian, ibid. at para. 35). Since it could well be argued that a command of
spelling and grammar does reflect skill and judgment, this remark suggests that McLachlin C.J. did
indeed have some qualitatively higher threshold in mind. An alternative view is that the amount of
editing work was not quantitatively sufficientbut this would reintroduce the consideration of labour.
Interestingly, in the American case Matthew Bender & Co. v. West Publishing Co., 158 F.3d 674 (2d
Cir. 1998) [Matthew Bender], cert. denied 522 U.S. 3732, 119 S. Ct. 2039, which also dealt with
copyright in published case reporters and which was not cited by the Canadian Supreme Court in
CCH Canadian, the court found no copyright in editorial work contained in the publishers law
reports on the basis that creativity in the task of creating a useful case report can only proceed in a
narrow groove (Matthew Bender, ibid. at 688).
24 See e.g. Thberge, supra note 9 at para. 32; Society of Composers, Authors and Music Publishers
of Canada v. Canadian Association of Internet Providers, [2004] 2 S.C.R. 427 at para. 132, 240
D.L.R. (4th) 193, 2004 SCC 45.
25 Feist, supra note 6 at 358.
261
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
bears significance. Creativity places more emphasis on the effort of the author to
create something new. Skill and judgment lacks this emphasis. Rather, it suggests
that care and thoughtfulness in working with known or pre-existing elements will
suffice. Such a standard of originality will likely present problems for courts faced
with complex copyright issues involving original facts. I use the term original
facts to refer to those facts that owe their existence to the exercise of individual
intellectual effort. Where authorial effort is described as skill and judgment and
facts are arrived at through an exercise in skill and judgment, one may question
whether the facts themselves have taken on a quality such that the protection of their
expression must amount to a protection of the facts themselves.
The problem of original facts can be illustrated through a consideration of two
recent Canadian cases. Both Weetman v. Baldwin26 and B & S Publications Inc. v.
Max-Contacts Inc.27 are lower-court decisions that predate CCH Canadian. In both
cases, the judges found that there was copyright infringement, notwithstanding that
the infringing act amounted to the copying of factual information. Although the
decisions can be dismissed either as being wrongly decided or reversible in light of
the recent decision in CCH Canadian, it is also possible that they might be decided
the same way today. Certainly in both cases, the judges were aware of the Tele-Direct
decision, which set an ostensibly higher threshold for copyright protection than did
CCH Canadian.28
In Weetman, Judge Romilly of the British Columbia Provincial Court dealt with a
case of alleged copyright infringement involving maps. The plaintiff, through some
significant personal effort, had located and charted a previously uncharted mountain
trail. The defendant had copied the trail location from the plaintiffs map. He argued,
inter alia, that the copying of the trail features from the plaintiffs map could not
infringe copyright because the features, which represented actual characteristics of
the landscape, amounted to facts. Judge Romilly rejected this argument, noting:
The state of Canadian law on the subject is that it is not open for someone
to argue that trails, roads and other features detailed with a precision and an
accuracy not previously attained by other mapmakers of the region in question,
which was facilitated by a particular process pioneered by a mapmaker, become
a compilation of facts to which everyone can copy and/or use without the
consent of the mapmaker because it has somehow been placed in the public
domain …29
26 2001 BCPC 292 [Weetman].
27 (2001), 287 A.R. 201 (Q.B.) [B & S Publications].
28 The Federal Court of Appeal in Tele-Direct, recast the skill, judgment or labour test as one
requiring skill, judgment and labour (supra note 2 at para. 28 [emphasis added]). While the
Supreme Court of Canada in CCH Canadian (supra note 1) does not expressly reject the Tele-Direct
standard, it excises labour from the test. It is unclear whether, in practical terms, the two versions are
significantly different. See Scassa, supra note 5.
29 Weetman, supra note 26 at para. 45.
[Vol. 51
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
262
In his view, Canadian law, in contrast to American law, would protect facts which
contain a certain level of creativity.30 Following CCH Canadian, Judge Romillys
views could be presented in these terms: the charting of the trail was a reflection of
skill and judgment, even though the actual location of the trail was also factual
information. The skill and judgment expended by the plaintiff to determine the
location of the trail and to arrive at the geographical data incorporated into his map
generated the originality necessary for copyright to subsist in the resultant map and its
specific features. On this view, the location of the trail is an original fact, arrived at
through authorial effort.
B & S Publications31 presents a slightly different situation. The case involved
alleged copying from the plaintiffs publication, the Oil and Gas Index. The Index
contained listings of explorers and producers in the oil and gas industry in Alberta,
along with additional factual information. Justice Hutchison held that the defendants
copying of the data violated the plaintiffs copyright, not in the selection and
arrangement of the data, but in the data itself. He noted:
I am of the opinion that the data relating to the exploration and production
companies as researched and presented by the plaintiff is capable of and by
itself of being copyrighted, owing in part to the criteria used to select the names
by the plaintiff, the research done on its currency and accuracy, and its
categorization.32
To put it in other words, Justice Hutchison seems to be saying that the original
selection of the data by the plaintiff was infringed by the copying of that original
selection, even though what was ultimately copied was factual information. It would
be difficult to say that the selection of facts was not copied, when the facts in that
format existed by virtue of the exercise of skill and judgment of the creator of the
work. If facts about these companies had not previously been selected to fit together,
or had not been previously organized in that constellation, one can understand the
view of Justice Hutchison. The copying of these facts from the plaintiffs work would
amount to a substantial taking of the original selection of the plaintiff, giving rise to
copyright infringement.
The key may lie in understanding what an original selection of facts is. Copyright
law protects an original selection of facts, independent of any original
arrangement.33 In the case of the Oil and Gas Index, it is possible to argue that the
court found it to be an original selection of facts. The copyright extended to the facts
themselves since independent creation would necessarily involve copying the core
protectable expression in the work: the selection. Indeed, in sweat of the brow
30 Ibid. at para. 46.
31 Supra note 27.
32 Ibid. at para. 44. Hutchison J. found that the design layout and format of the work was also
independently original and unique, and thus copyrightable.
33 The definition of compilation in the Copyright Act includes a work resulting from the selection
or arrangement of data (supra note 2, s. 2 [emphasis added]).
263
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
jurisdictions, a competitor is not free to reproduce facts contained in a compilation
without recreating and expending the efforts used to collect the facts. In such a
context, it is difficult to see the boundary between fact and expression. In some ways,
this approach is merely a statement of the doctrine of independent creation: as long as
the second author independently creates the same work without copying, there will
be no infringement.
The effect of such an approach is a monopoly over the facts themselves. In
economic terms, the competitor is faced with the choice of either recreating the
original efforts to collect the data (and thus the original expense), or paying a rent for
use of the information. One can question the efficiency of such an arrangement or its
benefit to society. Indeed, in Feist the US Supreme Court raised just that question.
The defendants refusal to licence the information to its competitor would have stifled
competition by causing the competitor to be faced with the inability to fully recreate
the data set and the expense of attempting to do so. It is also worth noting that the
term of monopoly for compilations of fact is the same as for any copyright-protected
work. Many commercial compilations of fact must be updated regularly to remain
current. Each update is arguably separately copyrightable, thus extending the
monopoly term either to perpetuity or at the very least, to a point past the useful life
of the compilation.
III. An Attempt to Define Facts
Part of the tension in the case law may be attributable to the use of the term fact
to refer to different kinds of information. A fact is defined as: a thing done, the
quality of being actual, something that has actual existence, an actual
occurrence, and a piece of information presented as having objective reality.34 The
array of definitions is interesting and demonstrates some nuance in the meaning of the
term. Some of the definitions point to actual (defined in turn as existing in fact or
reality),35 verifiable events. A trail through a mountain pass is a fact in this sense: it
exists in reality. The mapping of the trail is a description of that fact, and it would be
difficult to accurately describe it in map form in any other manner without
misrepresenting the fact of the trail and its precise parameters. A piece of
information presented as having objective reality is a whole other kind of fact,
however. A good lie amounts to a piece of information convincingly presented as
having objective reality, but lies are generally not regarded as facts. One could argue
that the dictionary definition should read a piece of information having objective
reality. This definition, however, may be underinclusive of things that might be
considered to be facts.
34 Websters Ninth New Collegiate Dictionary (Springfield, Mass.: Merriam-Webster, 1985) s.v.
fact.
35 Ibid., s.v. actual.
[Vol. 51
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
264
One of the problems with any discussion of copyright in facts lies in assumptions
about the meaning of the term fact and the impact of these assumptions on the
resultant analysis. Facts often do not exist in as plain and obvious a manner as, for
example, water flows downhill. Many facts do not need to be copied from
anywhere. They are widely or generally known, or they have been known for so long
that statutory monopoly terms are simply not relevant. Many so-called facts are
actually better described as information. In the discussion below, I will discuss
three categories of facts or information: information that is knowable only through
the exercise of significant skill and judgment; information that is interesting or
valuable only because of the way in which it has been selected or arranged; and
information that is not necessarily true. I will consider each of these categories in
turn.
It is worth reasserting that in my typology of facts, the term fact has been
replaced with information. Information is a more nuanced term that does not
embody the same bold claim to truth as the word fact.36 As I will argue, the term
fact is loaded and misleading. It suggests a certainty and permanence that can lead
to assumptions both that facts are distinct and recognizable and that they are excluded
from copyrightability because of some inherent characteristic of truth. The real debate
is about ownership in relation to the much more nuanced concept of information.
A. Information That Is Knowable Only Through the Exercise of
Considerable Skill and Judgment
Much scientific information falls into the category of information that is
knowable only through the exercise of considerable skill and judgment. Such
information, when it gains a certain level of acceptance, may be referred to as fact.
Scientific facts are sometimes challenged and disproved, however, even if they
have been accepted as facts for a significant period of time.37 Scientific facts are
essentially nothing more than information that is put forth as having objective
reality. Latour and Woolgar have characterized scientific endeavour in these terms:
the set of statements considered too costly to modify constitute what is referred to as
reality. Scientific activity is not about nature, it is a fierce fight to construct
reality.38 Scientific facts are essentially original facts. They are the product of labour,
36 In writing about fact in the context of journalism, one author asserts: There is no real
distinction between facts, information, and knowledge. They are all a result of interpretation through
communication practices that give them meaning in the contexts of their use (Richard V. Ericson,
The Future of Fact: How Journalists Visualize Fact (1998) 560 Annals 83 at 84).
37 For example, Gould recounts the sloppy science that resulted in the names Apatosaurus and
Brontosaurus being given to the same dinosaur. This anecdote is but one examplealbeit a notorious
oneof the displacement of scientific fact by later research and investigation. See Stephen Jay
Gould, Bully for Brontosaurus: Reflections in Natural History (New York: W.W. Norton, 1991) at 86-
90.
38 Bruno Latour & Steve Woolgar, Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts (Princeton,
N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1986) at 243 [emphasis in original].
265
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
capital investment, and considerable skill and judgment. They are expressive and
constitutive of reality, but they are not reality.
It is well accepted that there is no copyright in scientific fact; the results of
research are shared in scientific publications, and others are free to examine, discuss,
and test the data or theories presented. Scientists who wish to own the fruits of their
research must arrive at facts with industrial application, and must seek a patent.
Patent law is very clear that a patent must be for a new, nonobvious, and useful
invention;39 it is equally clear that an invention cannot include scientific principles,
abstract theorems, or discoveries.40 It is in the realm of scientific fact that we are most
closely wedded to the idea that facts are descriptors of the world around us.
Scientists may uncover facts, but they do not create them.
It is perhaps worth distinguishing here between raw data, which may represent
recorded observations, and the theories that flow from conjecture about the meaning
of an aggregate of recorded observations. The theory is an abstract idea, which is also
not protectable under copyright law. Theories are not necessarily facts, although some
theories are treated as fact.41 Raw data is arguably a collection of fact, although even
here the sands shift; different scientists studying the same questions may generate
different data depending upon their methodology and resources. Suffice it to say that
patent law regards neither raw data nor abstract theories as protectable. Copyright
law, at least ostensibly, similarly rejects the protection of facts or ideas.
B. Information That Is Useful or Valuable Only Because of the Way
in Which It Has Been Selected or Arranged
Scientific facts, discussed above, are often original in the sense of being the
product of a significant expenditure of skill and judgment. There is another category
of facts, however, which in and of themselves are not particularly original, but
which take on value because of the effort put into their selection or arrangement. The
facts in B & S Publications42 are an example of this kind of fact. Information about
players in the Alberta oil patch is not original to the recorders of this information, but
the selection and arrangement of the information into a directory gives the
information a particular value. It is valuable because it has been mined or extracted
from a range of available information to serve a specific purpose.
39 See e.g. the definition of invention in the Patent Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. P-4, s. 2 [Patent Act]. See
also Patent Act, ibid. ss. 28.2, 28.3.
40 The Patent Act expressly excludes scientific principles and abstract theorems from patentability
(ibid., s. 27(8)). Discoveries are excluded by virtue of jurisprudential principles. See e.g. Pioneer Hi-
Bred Ltd. v. Canada (Commissioner of Patents), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 1623 at 1634, 60 D.L.R. (4th) 223.
41 For example, many consider evolution to be a fact, while it is actually a theory.
42 Supra note 27.
[Vol. 51
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
266
The telephone directory information at issue in Feist43 and Tele-Direct44 in some
ways falls into this category. In these cases, the respective courts made it clear that
only an original selection or arrangement of facts would give rise to copyright in the
compilation of data, and the copyright would not extend beyond the particular
selection or arrangement. Because Feist and Tele-Direct dealt with alphabetical
telephone directory information in which the selection of facts was dictated either by
legislation or by custom, the cases presented the lowest possible level of authorial
effort. In fact, no copyright was found to subsist in the listings in either case. These
cases, however, are not typical of the scenarios that will likely arise for works in this
category. B & S Publications is just one example of a case where the selection of facts
for a directory can be considered original; there are others.45 The challenge in such
cases will be to maintain a distinction between the originality in the selection of the
data and the underlying data itself.46
It is interesting to compare the tension over the originality of selection or
arrangement of facts in this category of facts. In theory, a scientist, through the
development of an empirical methodology, selects not only the subject of her study,
but also plays a role in defining the boundaries of her results. The data that result
from the experiment are therefore the result of an original selection of facts. Yet it is
generally not considered even arguable that a scientist might hold a copyright in the
empirical data she generates. In the commercial context, however, the protection to be
afforded to a selection of data is a matter of great debate.
The significance of this category is that the value of a work truly does lie in the
selection and arrangement of the information, or its aggregation, rather than in the
underlying pieces of information. In such a context, the authors contribution to the
work is external to the underlying facts or information contained in the work. It is this
category of works that has provided the most significant challenge to copyright law.
The statute seeks to protect the authors original contribution by describing it as a
selection or arrangement,47 and extends copyright protection to that contribution.
As will be argued, however, it is crucial to maintain a distinction between the
authorial effort involved in selecting or arranging data and the data itself. Once
43 Supra note 6.
44 Supra note 2.
45 In Key Publications Inc. v. Chinatown Today Publishing Enterprises Inc., 945 F.2d 509 (2d Cir.
1991) [Key Publications], a selection of directory listings for Chinese-American businesses was
considered to be sufficiently original to give rise to copyright protection.
46 In Key Publications (ibid.), the court found that the listings were sufficiently original to attract
copyright protection, but also ruled that the copyright was not infringed by the competitors product
because of a lack of sufficient overlap. On the facts, there was little similarity between the two
directories. The court in this case struggled with the application of the principles in Feist (supra note
6). While accepting that copyright in a compilation of facts is thin, the court noted that we do not
believe it is anorexic (Key Publications, ibid. at 514). Further, the court stated: What must be shown
is substantial similarity between those elements, and only those elements, that provide copyrightability
to the allegedly infringed compilation (ibid.) in other words, the selection or arrangement of facts.
47 See the definition of compilation in the Copyright Act (supra note 2, s. 2).
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
protection is effectively extended to facts contained in a compilation (as in B & S
Publications), the rationale for withholding copyright protection from other kinds of
facts, such as the location of mountain trails, disappears.
267
C. Information That Is Not Necessarily True
Information that is not necessarily true is my third category of fact. This
category could be described as representing filtered or mediated fact. These are the
facts that make up our accounts of the world around us: they are present in news
reports, anecdotes, biographies, histories, and so on. Filtered or mediated facts are
woven into a tale told about the world around us. They are put forth as truth but are
coloured by perspective.
The classic case International News Service v. Associated Press48 provides a good
illustration. In that case, the US Supreme Court stated that there was no copyright in
information. It also concluded that the plaintiffs news reports from the front lines of
World War I could not be protected from the copying of the substance of the reports,
on the basis that the facts contained in the reports were not part of the copyright in the
underlying news articles. Justice Pitney, writing for the majority of the court, seemed
to accept, however, that there was a certain authorial effort involved in generating the
information contained in news reports. He wrote: news matter, however little
susceptible of ownership or dominion in the absolute sense, is stock in trade, to be
gathered at the cost of enterprise, organization, skill, labor, and money ….49 He also
recognized that part of the exchange value of news lay in its novelty and freshness,
the regularity of the service, its reputed reliability and thoroughness, and its
adaptability to the public needs.50 In this statement, Justice Pitney seems to accept
that it is not essential that the information excluded from copyright protection be
objectively true. Objective truth is not the basis for excluding the information from
copyright protection. It is certainly the case that some information reported from the
front lines would be verifiable and true, but it is also likely that some information
might actually be erroneous, some might be presented in a highly selective manner,
which gives a less than accurate overall picture of events, and some might be
downright falseproduced as part of the inevitable propaganda machinery of war.
Yet it fits the definition of information presented as having objective reality,
regardless of whether it actually has objective reality. This approach to facts is
pragmatic, as it would likely be too difficult to engage in an analysis of what bits of
information are fact, which are fiction, and which aggregates of fact amount to fiction
or partial fiction because they are so selective.
48 248 U.S. 215, 39 S. Ct. 68 (1918) [INS cited to U.S.].
49 Ibid. at 236.
50 Ibid. at 238.
[Vol. 51
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
268
Gordon has argued that some information has a hybrid quality,51 placing it on the
boundary of fact and creative work. She notes that creative works can be used
factuallyas illustrations of history, culture, or as threads in the argument of a
subsequent authors work. If an authors statements in personal correspondence are
treated as creative works rather than facts when used by a subsequent biographer,
then copyright law can be used by the first author to restrain or constrain the
biographers works.52 Significantly, courts in the United States have been hesitant to
extend copyright protection to even highly speculative fact. In Nash v. CBS Inc.,53
the court ruled that a movie that embraced the plaintiffs theory that John Dillinger
was not actually dead, but living on the west coast, did not violate the copyright in the
plaintiffs book that developed this theory. The court referred to Hoehling v.
Universal City Studios Inc., to the effect that [t]o avoid a chilling effect on authors
who contemplate tackling an historical issue or event, broad latitude must be granted
to subsequent authors who make use of historical subject matter, including theories or
plots.54 This American case law recognizes that facts do not have to be true or
even verifiable to be excluded from copyright protection.
In the above typology of facts, it is clear that the middle categorycompilations
of factis the category that has proven most difficult for the courts to deal with. It is
often accepted that the information in the compilation is true, and that it is useful
because of the way in which it is organized or because it has been gathered in one
place for the first time. The other categoriesinvolving scientific fact or filtered or
mediated informationhave proven less difficult for the courts, perhaps because it is
easier to recognize the real public value in any debate, discussion, or critique of the
information presented, or in the presentation of alternate versions or interpretations of
the same information. The expressions of both scientific and mediated facts are
protected by copyright law, while the underlying facts themselves are in the public
domain. With compilations of fact, courts are willing to protect the expression of the
facts, in terms of their selection and arrangement, but they have struggled with the
separation of the facts from the expression. Protecting the expression only gives
limited protection to the work as a whole, in part because the expression is more
mechanical or function driven than in the other categories of information I have
discussed. Yet this is precisely why, as the US Supreme Court stated in Feist,
copyright in a factual compilation is thin.55 Attempts to broaden the scope of
protection for such works ultimately will protect the facts along with their expression.
51 Wendy J. Gordon, Reality as Artifact: From Feist to Fair Use (1992) 55 Law & Contemp.
Probs. 93.
52 Ibid. at 100. She strongly criticizes the appellate court decision in Salinger v. Random House, 650
F. Supp. 413 (S.D. N.Y. 1986), revd, 811 F. 2d 90 (2d Cir. 1987).
53 899 F.2d 1537 (7th Cir. 1990) [Nash].
54 618 F.2d 972 at 978 (2d Cir. 1980) [Hoehling].
55 Feist, supra note 6 at 349.
269
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
IV. Copyright and Facts
The widely stated principle that there is no copyright in facts has reached the
status of an axiom across most comparable jurisdictions. In Australia,56 Canada,57 and
the United States,58 for example, the principle is wholeheartedly embraced, even
though each jurisdiction has arrived at a different standard for originality in
copyright.59 It is significant that in all three jurisdictions, the principle that facts are
not copyrightable has been linked to the originality requirement.60 As the theory goes,
facts inherently do not owe their existence to any authorial effort. A fact, so it is said,
exists independently of the authors who may express the fact, but who can only
obtain rights over their particular expression of the fact.61
Even accepting this simplistic view of facts, the situation becomes more complex
when considering the status of fact-based works, such as compilations of fact. The
definition of compilation in section 2 of the Copyright Act includes a work
resulting from the selection or arrangement of data.62 This definition has been
interpreted to mean that copyright law does not protect the facts in a compilation, but
only the original selection or arrangement of those facts.63 The work that is protected
is that which results from the authorial effort of selecting and/or arranging the facts.
It is much easier to see how an original arrangement of facts can be protected
separately from the underlying facts. The arrangement of the facts is patent and
56 Telstra Corporation Ltd. v. Desktop Marketing Systems Pty Ltd. (2001), 181 A.L.R. 134 at para 46
(F.C.A.) [Telstra].
57 CCH Canadian, supra note 1 at para. 22.
58 In the U.S., [t]hat there can be no valid copyright in facts is universally understood (Feist, supra
note 6 at 344, OConnor J.).
59 The United States requires a minimal degree of creativity (Feist, ibid. at 345); Australia
recognizes industriousness or sweat of the brow (Telstra, supra note 56 at paras. 85-88). The
Supreme Court of Canada, in setting a standard of skill and judgment (CCH Canadian, supra note 1
at para. 16) has claimed what it believes to be the middle ground between these positions.
60 This link is most explicit in Feist where OConnor J. states that the reason why facts are not
copyrightable is because facts do not owe their origin to an act of authorship. The distinction is one
between creation and discovery: The first person to find and report a particular fact has not created the
fact; he or she has merely discovered its existence (supra note 6 at 347). In CCH Canadian,
McLachlin C.J. notes: OConnor J.s concerns about the sweat of the brow doctrines improper
extension of copyright over facts also resonate in Canada (supra note 1 at para. 22). In Telstra, the
court notes that the requisite originality cannot be found in the facts themselves, only in an original
selection or arrangement of the facts (supra note 56 at paras. 46-47).
61 OConnor J. explains it thus: [I]f the compilation author clothes facts with an original collocation
of words, he or she may be able to claim a copyright in this written expression. Others may copy the
underlying facts from the publication, but not the precise words used to present them (Feist, ibid. at
348).
62 Supra note 2, s. 2.
63 Tele-Direct, supra note 2 at para. 17. See also Feist, supra note 6 at 349.
[Vol. 51
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
270
obvious in the work itself.64 Facts might be arranged according to particular
categories developed by the creator of the work. For example, assume an author
decides to create a list of all Supreme Court of Canada decisions ever rendered. She
might choose to organize these chronologically or alphabetically. Either of these
modes would be an arrangement of the facts: the cases decided by the Court. In both
instances, there would likely be issues as to the originality of her arrangement. In
other words, following CCH Canadian, it seems difficult to argue that the author
could prevent anyone else from copying her alphabetical list of cases decided by the
Supreme Court of Canada. She might, however, decide to list them in order of
importance. It would involve some intellectual effort on her part to decide which
cases, viewed in their social and historical context, were most important. Someone
who copied the ordering of this list would be copying the authors original
arrangement. In either case, the arrangement of the facts is obvious on the face of
things; the issue is whether the arrangement reflects an exercise of skill and judgment.
An original selection is more problematic. The character, usefulness, reliability,
or value of the work may turn on the quality of effort made in selecting the facts that
are presented. As a result, in some cases the act of selecting facts may appear to
amount to an authorial effort by virtue of the skill and judgment exercised in selecting
the facts to include. For example, as long as the author decides to include in her list
all decisions of the Supreme Court of Canada, it is unlikely that she will be able to
argue she has made an original selection. If, however, she were to decide to select the
one hundred most important decisions, there would presumably be a degree of skill
and judgment involved in making this selection. Although copyright law only
protects the selection or arrangement of facts in a compilation of facts, where the
selection of facts is considered to be sufficiently original to attract copyright
protection, the reproduction of the selection and the reproduction of the facts
themselves can effectively merge.65 Anyone who copied the authors list of the one
64 In Feist, the arrangement of facts in the telephone directory was alphabetical. The court found this
arrangement to be insufficiently original, and described it as garden-variety (ibid. at 362).
65 In the recent Ontario Court of Appeal decision in Robertson v. Thomson Corp. (2004) 72 O.R.
(3d) 481, 243 D.L.R. (4th) 257 (C.A.), a key issue was whether the collective work that was each
issue of the Globe and Mail was reproduced in the defendants electronic database of articles. The
majority found that the collective work was not reproduced in the database, in part because the bulk of
value-added material in the newspapers, such as advertisements, photos, photo captions, stock market
and financial tables, birth and death notices, illustrations, cross references, whats inside, teasers and
weather forecasts were not included in the database, and [t]he masthead, size of the headline, fonts,
column width and number columns are not visible (ibid. at para. 12). Blair J.A., in dissent, would
have characterized the contribution of the editors differently. Rather than place such an emphasis on
quantifiable content, he emphasized a more qualitative approach to assessing contribution: [T]he
electronic version found in the database retains the heart of the newspaperthe portion that gives it its
essence as a newspapernamely, its editorial vision, as expressed through the editors selection and
editing of its news stories, its articles, and its editorial content (ibid. at para. 138). The difference
between the two views is arguably that Blair J.A. placed more emphasis on selection as a form of
authorship, and selection is inherently represented in the contents themselves.
271
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
hundred most important Supreme Court of Canada decisions would be copying her
original selection; it becomes difficult to separate the protection of her original
selection from the protection of the actual contents of the list.66
In Telstra,67 the Australian Federal Court, while accepting that there was no
copyright in facts, nonetheless extended a copyright-type protection to facts within a
compilation. It found copyright in the compilation using a sweat of the brow
standard of originality. For the court, the logical extension of finding copyright in a
compilation of facts that owed its existence to the expenditure of labour on the part of
the creator of the compilation was to protect the underlying facts against reproduction
in other works.68
Translating this approach into the context of a skill and judgment standard for
originality gives rise to a similar set of problems. While the telephone directory at
issue in Telstra may fall below the standard set by the Supreme Court of Canada
because the labour involved would not meet the necessary level of skill and
judgment, other factual compilations will pose challenges. With some compilations,
the selection of facts, through an exercise in skill and judgment, may be the essence
of the work. A reproduction of that selection of facts would be copyright
infringement; a substantial reproduction of that selection of facts would also be
copyright infringement. At a certain point, it becomes difficult to separate the facts
from the original selection that is the subject matter of copyright. In other words,
while in theory one does not have copyright in an atomistic, individualized fact, ones
copyright in an original selection of facts may substantially protect those facts from
copying.
As discussed above, courts in Canada, the United States, and elsewhere have
taken the view that copyright law does not protect facts. In this section, I will explore
the reasons put forward by various courts in support of this proposition. I will argue
that it is of fundamental importance to properly understand the reason for the
exclusion of facts from copyright law, and that courts have not been consistent in
their articulation of the reason for the exclusion.
66 Ginsburg argues, similarly, that works of selection are even more deserving of copyright
protection than works of arrangement in the context of electronic databases (supra note 4).
67 Supra note 56.
68 For example, even though the selection and arrangement of the facts was different in many
respects, the court found infringement:
As regards the directories, the significant recorded facts (name, address, telephone
number and the relevant type of business) are the same, or substantially the same, as
they appear in Telstras works. While there are differences, they are in the detail. For
example, when displayed on a screen, the information from the CD-ROM does not
appear as columns on a page. But the information can be retrieved in alphabetical order
(by postcode rather than region) and can be examined in much the same way as one
would read a column on a page. The fact that the alphabetical listings are by postcode
and not region, is not a material difference. Nor is the fact that portions of the
advertisements are not reproduced (Telstra, ibid. at para. 109).
272
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
[Vol. 51
A. United States
In INS,69 the US Supreme Court ruled that copyright law could not protect the
information set out in newspaper accounts of front line battles. Justice Pitney, for the
majority, emphasized the importance of distinguishing between the substance of the
information and the particular form or collocation of words in which the writer has
communicated it.70 He went on to note that the news elementthe information
respecting current events contained in the literary productionis not the creation of
the writer, but is a report of matters that ordinarily are publici juris; it is the history of
the day.71 This statement is an extremely important articulation of the reason for
excluding facts from copyright protection. First, the facts at issue in the case are
characterized as information. The majority of the court views this information as
falling into the public domain: it is the history of the day, not capable of private
ownership.
The principle underlying the INS decision is also apparent in the more modern
Miller v. Universal City Studios Inc.72 In that case, it was argued that the research into
the facts of a particular event was, by virtue of the skill and effort expended to gather
and compile the research, copyrightable. The US Court of Appeals for the Fifth
Circuit rejected this argument on public policy grounds. After stating the somewhat
problematic proposition that authors merely discover facts, and do not author them,
the court emphasized:
The line drawn between uncopyrightable facts and copyrightable expression of
facts serves an important purpose in copyright law. It provides a means of
balancing the publics interest in stimulating creative activity … against the
publics need for unrestrained access to information. It allows a subsequent
author to build upon and add to prior accomplishments without unnecessary
duplication of effort.73
The statement regarding the public domain and public policy underlying the
exclusion of facts from copyright protection is significant, and builds on cases such as
INS. In Hoehling,74 dating just shortly before the Miller decision, the US Court of
Appeals for the Second Circuit also expressed the view that
the protection afforded the copyright holder has never extended to history, be it
documented fact or explanatory hypothesis. The rationale for this doctrine is
that the cause of knowledge is best served when history is the common
property of all, and each generation remains free to draw upon the discoveries
and insights of the past.75
69 Supra note 48.
70 Ibid. at 234.
71 Ibid.
72 650 F.2d 1365 (5th Cir. 1981) [Miller].
73 Ibid. at 1371-72.
74 Supra note 54.
75 Ibid. at 974.
273
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
The court in Hoehling limited copyright protection to the authors original
expression of particular facts and theories already in the public domain.76
Hoehling and Miller are important cases in that both express the underlying
public policy for excluding facts from copyright protection. They also both clearly
recognize a complex understanding of the term fact. Rather than describe facts as
some form of observable truth, both courts recognize that facts may include theories,
hypotheses, or even particular accounts of facts. The cases must also be understood,
however, in light of the kind of facts that were at issue. In both cases, the facts would
have fallen into my third category: information that is not necessarily true. Within this
category, it is clear that courts are reluctant to render decisions which may seal off
such facts from open discussion, criticism, and challenge. Ginsburg notes that,
ironically, courts have (at least prior to Feist) often afforded greater protection to
mere compilations of fact:
In the realm of high authorship, some decisions express fear of monopolization
of historical or other facts, and therefore exclude from copyrights ambit all but
the authors choice and ordering of words. On the other hand, some courts
acknowledge the low authorship of compilations such as address lists, yet
extend copyright protection not merely to the information in the particular form
presented in plaintiffs work, but to other formats that might be imposed upon
the collected data.77
In this context, the US Supreme Court decision in Feist is particularly significant: it
attempts to place all categories of fact on the same footing.
Although Feist expressly follows INS and cites Miller with approval, and
although the US Supreme Court in Feist forcefully restates the principle that there can
be no copyright in facts, Justice OConnor appears to put forward a rationale that
places more emphasis on the concept of originality and less on the public domain.
Writing for a unanimous court, she begins by stating the basic principle in fairly
absolute terms: That there can be no valid copyright in facts is universally
understood. The most fundamental axiom of copyright law is that [n]o author may
copyright his ideas or the facts he narrates.78 She does not, however, explain this
principle in terms of the public domain. Rather, she notes: The key to resolving the
tension lies in understanding why facts are not copyrightable. The sine qua non of
copyright is originality.79 The US Supreme Court thus explains the fact/expression
dichotomy in terms of the concept of originality. Facts are not copyrightable, because
they are not original to the author:
No one may claim originality as to facts. … This is because facts do not owe
their origin to an act of authorship. The distinction is one between creation and
discovery: The first person to find and report a particular fact has not created
76 Ibid.
77 Ginsburg, supra note 4 at 1894 [footnotes omitted].
78 Feist, supra note 6 at 344-45.
79 Ibid. at 345.
274
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
[Vol. 51
the fact; he or she has merely discovered its existence. To borrow from Burrow-
Giles, one who discovers a fact is not its maker or originator. … The
discoverer merely finds and records. … Census takers, for example, do not
create the population figures that emerge from their efforts; in a sense, they
copy these figures from the world around them.80
This view is supported by Nimmer, who writes:
No one may claim originality as to facts. Facts may be discovered, but they are
not created by an act of authorship. One who discovers an otherwise unknown
fact may well have performed a socially useful function, but the discovery as
such does not render him an author in either the constitutional or statutory
sense.81
The rationale set out both by Nimmer and in Feist shifts the focus of the analysis to
the link between the concept of originality and the uncopyrightability of facts. Facts
are thus assumed to be inherently true statements or representations of objective
reality, although Nimmer goes on to state that an interpretation of fact is itself a fact,
or purported fact, deduced from other facts.82 While it is significant that Justice
OConnor would place all facts in the public domain, the rationale for doing so is no
less important. A fact that is in the public domain because it represents a truth
available to all who make the effort to discover it is in the public domain for a
different reason than facts that are in the public domain because it is better for society
to have free and open access to that information than not.83 Further, the alignment of
facts with objective truth leaves room for the argument that some information is
capable of ownership because of the authorial effort invested in arriving at it.84
B. Canada
Canadian copyright law has struggled with original facts. In Ascot,85 the British
Columbia Supreme Court dealt with an argument of copyright infringement in
relation to rival horse-racing publications. The substance of what had been taken from
the plaintiffs publication was factual material about the races. Its arrangement in the
80 Ibid. at 347 [references omitted].
81 Melville B. Nimmer & David Nimmer, Nimmer on Copyright, looseleaf (New York: Matthew
Bender, 1963) vol. 2 at 2-178.2(3) [footnotes omitted].
82 Ibid. [footnotes omitted].
83 Drassinower makes the following assertions about the public domain: One might say that the
public domain is not only a space containing freely available materials. It is also a fundamental
condition of free and equal interaction between persons in their capacity as authors. The publics
domain is the domain of fair interaction (Abraham Drassinower, A Rights-Based View of the
Idea/Expression Dichotomy in Copyright Law (2003) 16 Can. J. L. & Jur. 3 at 10).
84 Nimmer is adamant that a fact cannot be authored: The discovery of a fact, regardless of the
quantum of labor and expense, is simply not the work of an author (supra note 81 at 2-178.2(15)
[emphasis in original, footnotes omitted]). The view of facts as discoverable, however, is an
oversimplification of the concept.
85 Supra note 21.
275
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
plaintiffs work was considered by the court to be of a kind universally used at North
American race tracks. Nevertheless, the court ruled that the plaintiff had copyright in
the material. Justice Macdonald found that the plaintiffs efforts in preparing the
publication warranted copyright protection. His reasons were not based on an
expenditure of effort alone, however. He wrote: In settling the conditions of the
races some knowledge, experience and exercise of judgment were required.86 Justice
Macdonald concluded: there is material, originated by the plaintiff, and involving
sufficient labour, knowledge and judgment to support copyright.87
On a similar set of facts, the British Columbia Court of Appeal reached a similar
result in B.C. Jockey Club.88 As in Ascot, the plaintiff published factual information
relating to the particular races to be run, including their dates and times, the purses,
horses, jockeys, weather and track conditions, and so on. In his rival publication, the
defendant had reproduced a great deal of this information. It was provided in a
substantially different format, however, alongside additional original content. The
Court of Appeal affirmed the decision of the trial judge, who found copyright
infringement on the basis that the defendant has made a substantial use of all the
essential facts compiled by the Club.89 In particular, the trial judge ruled:
Although he adopted that information to his own style and added
information of his own, the defendant nevertheless appropriated a substantial
amount of the work, skill, judgment and knowledge of the Club. The copyright
of the Club does not reside solely in the order of the information which it has
compiled. Although the defendant has rearranged and republished that
information in a different style, he nevertheless continued to appropriate a
substantial part of the Clubs original work.90
Although B.C. Jockey Club is often cited as an example of the sweat of the brow
line of cases in Canada, it is clear from this quoted passage that the facts in the
plaintiffs publication were not protected solely because of the effort required to
compile them. The compilation as a whole reflected the work, skill, judgment and
knowledge of the Club.91 As with Ascot, this compilation would fall into my second
category of original facts: facts that are interesting or valuable only because of the
way in which they have been selected or arranged. In the Court of Appeals view, the
act of selection gives the facts value; thus, selecting from the selection amounts to
infringement of that which is original in the work. It is interesting to note that neither
the Federal Court of Appeal in Tele-Direct,92 nor the Supreme Court of Canada in CCH
86 Ibid. at 421.
87 Ibid. at 422.
88 Supra note 21.
89 B.C. Jockey Club (S.C.), ibid. at 703.
90 Ibid. at 703-704 [emphasis added].
91 Ibid.
92 Supra note 2.
[Vol. 51
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
276
Canadian93 address or engage with the problem presented in this case. As noted earlier,
the same reasoning resurfaces in a post-Tele-Direct context in B & S Publications.94
The category of facts that are not really facts is clearly treated differently by the
courts, perhaps because it is an instance where facts are more obviously akin to ideas.
Judges seem to find it easier to keep ideas safely in the public domain. Deeks v.
Wells,95 an Ontario case from the 1930s, dealt with an accusation by the plaintiff that
copyright in her historical work had been infringed by the defendant in a competing
work. Justice Orde of the Court of Appeal noted that:
There can be no copyright in the facts of history or in their chronological
sequence. Had The Web been published, the defendant Wells was as free to
consult and use it in the preparation of his work as the plaintiff was to consult
and use The Encyclopaedia Britannica or any other publication as a source of
information. Infringement of copyright in such cases must, as a general rule,
consist of the copying of the words of another in the order in which he has used
them. The use of the same historical facts or of the same ideas is not enough.96
The decision of the Court was later affirmed by the Judicial Committee of the Privy
Council. Lord Atkin observed:
neither Miss Deeks nor Mr. Wells was present at the beginning of the world or
until a very considerable time later, and they have had to rely upon the
accumulation of information which has been made by many authors before
them and to which they have had to have recourse in writing such a work as
this.97
These decisions take the position that in fact-based works of writing, copyright
infringement can arise only through the copying of the writing, but not the underlying
facts.
C. Facts and the Public Domain
Facts that meet the definition of information presented as having objective
reality are often the product of an exercise of skill and judgment. These facts are the
kind that might tempt a court to protect the underlying factual information from
copying. Yet we know from the same cases that set the standard for originality that
facts are not copyrightable. There is tension between these propositions.
93 Supra note 1.
94 Supra note 27.
95 (1932), [1933] 1 D.L.R. 353 (P.C.) [Deeks (P.C.)], affg [1931] O.R. 831, [1931] 4 D.L.R. 533
(C.A.) [Deeks (C.A.) cited to O.R.], affg (1930), [1931] O.R. 818, [1930] 4 D.L.R. 513 (H.C.).
96 Deeks (C.A.), ibid. at 847. Ginsburg argues that the facts in works of high authorship such as the
one at issue in Deeks deserve less protection since limiting copyrights reach to the first authors
subjective contributions to the facts not only frees second authors from having to account for all the
sources, but it also leaves the first author with extensive protectable material (supra note 4 at 1915).
97 Deeks (P.C.), supra note 95 at 358.
277
T. SCASSA ORIGINAL FACTS
2006]
The tension can be resolved by reference to the concept of the public domain and
the public policy underlying copyright law. If facts are excluded from copyright
monopolies, it is either because they are not considered to be the product of
someones authorial effort, or because some efforts are made for the common good
and not for reward through copyright monopolies.98 It is difficult to see how one can
say that many so-called facts are not the product of someones authorial effort. The
gathering of facts of a battle from the front lines during wartime involves a certain
authorial effort on the part of the reporter. Not only do they go to great lengths in
difficult circumstances to gather the information, they presumably observe, question,
attempt to verify information, rely on confidential sources, and so on. If this authorial
effort is not to be recognized as giving rights in the facts as reported, it must be
because there is some public good that is seen as being served by having certain kinds
or categories of information in the public domain. If this is the case, then when
information is put forward as having objective reality, it should fall into the public
domain so that it can be tested, challenged, critiqued, verified, or disproved. The same
is true of scientific facts.
Conclusion
The category of facts that are useful or valuable because of the way in which they
have been selected or arranged poses unique difficulties. The underlying facts
themselves are simply facts, and there is no basis on which they should receive
copyright protection. But the author of the compilation, through her selection and
arrangement of these facts, has created a work. The Copyright Act99 specifically
accepts this type of work as a compilation. As noted above, it can be difficult to
separate what is original in a selection of facts from the facts themselves. Certainly
using the Supreme Court of Canadas standard of skill and judgment as a test for
originality does little to help in this analysis.
The public policy motivation for excluding facts from copyright monopolies has
nothing to do with whatever authorial effort might go into their generation or
creation.100 It is important to keep this idea in mind when working with the Supreme
Court of Canadas skill and judgment standard, as it would be relatively easy to use
98 Drassinower argues that the law of copyright protects the authors expression, but not her ideas,
even where the latter are assumed to be as much a product of the authors labour as the former. Hence,
the point is not that labour is irrelevant to the constitution of copyright but rather that the legal
meaning of the authors labour cannot … be derived from the category of labour itself (Drassinower,
supra note 83 at 9 [footnotes omitted]). This same point can be made with respect to fact-based works:
the authors original expression of the facts are protected, not the underlying factsnotwithstanding
that the facts may have been arrived at through an exercise of skill and judgment.
99 Supra note 2, s. 2.
100 In writing about copyright and facts, Gordon notes: In a civilized nation, much of reality is
artifact. Too broad a set of intellectual property rights can give one set of persons control over how
that reality is viewed, perceived, interpretedcontrol over what the world means (supra note 51 at
101 [emphasis in original]).
[Vol. 51
MCGILL LAW JOURNAL / REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
278
this standard to find copyright in a variety of information that has been generated, not
simply through labour or the investment of capital, but also through the exercise of
skill and judgment. That the Supreme Court recognized that facts are not
copyrightable and that skill and judgment is the threshold standard for originality
suggests that any assessment of skill and judgment as the authorial effort needed to
give rise to copyright should exclude the putting forth of information as having
objective reality. Facts, like ideas, are in the public domain. The public is better
served by being allowed to reproduce these facts, to argue about them, write about
them, challenge them, replicate them.
If this approach is to be considered part of the copyright bargain with society, one
might wonder how whole categories of creators of works that are facts are not just
limited in their copyright protection, but excluded in terms of the most valuable
dimension of their work. A scientist can have copyright in the paper in which he or
she expresses the results of research, but has no copyright in the facts or data
generated from the experiments. Similarly, in another context, the compiler of facts in
a directory has copyright in the selection and arrangement of those facts, but not in
the factual content, which is the most valuable aspect of the directory. In the scientific
realm, the answer may be in part that most researchers work in salaried or grant-paid
positions, and the continued receipt of their salary or the possibility to generate new
grants is sufficient incentive for continued creative production. In the context of the
generation of commercial fact-based works such as directories, the answer is less
clear. Presumably, even absent copyright protection there is still some incentive to
produce these works; the works may feature as only one aspect of a companys
business model, for example, as a value-added element of a broader package of
services. Most directory-type works are only of value for a very limited period of time
in any event. Without frequent revisions and updates they become marginally useful
quite quickly. The value of such products, particularly in an information age, may
come from the reliability and frequency of update services provided, as well as from
ease of accessibility and various modes of accessibility.
The new skill and judgment standard of protection thus leaves judges faced
with copyright claims over fact-based works with two options. The standard is open-
ended enough to be used to extend copyright protection to the data in compilations of
fact: the Courts middle ground is actually a swamp. Yet it is also possible to read
the decision so as to exclude copyright protection for the underlying facts. While the
first option may allow a judge to satisfy his or her inclination towards an equitable
result in a case of perceived unfair competition, the second must prevail if we are to
be serious about fostering a robust public domain and the corresponding free flow of
information and ideas in the broader public interest.