McGill Law Journal Revue de droit de McGill
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL
AMENDMENT RULES
Richard Albert*
formal amendments but
The current scholarly focus on informal con-
stitutional amendment has obscured the continu-
ing relevance of formal amendment rules. In this
article, I return our attention to formal amend-
ment in order to show that formal amendment
rulesnot
formal
amendment rules themselvesperform an un-
derappreciated function: to express constitutional
values. Drawing from national constitutions, in
particular the Canadian, South African, German,
and United States constitutions, I illustrate how
constitutional designers may deploy
formal
amendment rules to create a formal constitutional
hierarchy that reflects special political commit-
ments. That formal amendment rules may express
constitutional values is both a clarifying and a
complicating contribution to their study. This the-
sis clarifies the study of formal amendment rules
by showing that such rules may serve a function
that scholars have yet to attribute to them; yet it
complicates this study by indicating that the con-
stitutional text alone cannot prove whether the
constitutional values expressed in formal amend-
ment rules represent authentic or inauthentic po-
litical commitments.
Laccent acadmique actuel sur lamende-
ment informel dune constitution a obscurci la per-
tinence continue de la procdure formelle damen-
dement. Dans cet article, je rapporte notre atten-
tion sur lamendement formel pour montrer que la
procdure formelle (non pas la modification, mais
la procdure elle-mme) remplit un rle sous-
valu : lexpression des valeurs constitutionnelles.
En mappuyant sur des constitutions nationales, en
particulier celles du Canada, de lAfrique du Sud,
de lAllemagne et des tats-Unis, je dmontre que
les auteurs insrent parfois des rgles formelles
damendement pour crer une formelle hirarchie
qui reflte des engagements particuliers de nature
politique. Lexpression possible des valeurs consti-
tutionnelles faite par des rgles formelles damen-
dement est une contribution qui clarifie et com-
plique leur tude. Cette conclusion clarifie ltude
des rgles formelles damendement en montrant
que de telles rgles peuvent servir une fonction
que les rudits ny ont pas encore attribu. Cepen-
dant, elle complique cette tude en indiquant que
le texte constitutionnel seul est incapable de prou-
ver si les valeurs constitutionnelles exprimes dans
les rgles formelles damendement reprsentent
des engagements de nature politique, quils soient
authentiques ou inauthentiques.
* Assistant Professor, Boston College Law School; Yale University (J.D., B.A.); Oxford
University (B.C.L.); Harvard University (LL.M.). Email: richard.albert@bc.edu. For
helpful comments and conversations, I thank Carlos Bernal-Pulido, Brannon Denning,
Rosalind Dixon, Oran Doyle, Tom Ginsburg, Claudia Haupt, Ran Hirschl, Rick Kay,
Mark Kende, David Landau, Will Partlett, Vlad Perju, Arie Rosen, Yaniv Roznai, Ozan
Varol, Tom Kohler, and John Vile. I am grateful for the useful suggestions and criti-
cisms I received from the three anonymous external reviewers who recommended this
submission for publication. I have also benefitted from presenting earlier versions of
this article at Indiana UniversityMcKinney School of Law, the University of San
Francisco Law School, the 2013 Annual Meeting of the Law & Society Association, and
in the 201213 AADS works-in-progress lecture series at Boston College. I am also
grateful to the editors of the McGill Law Journal for their outstanding editorial contri-
butions to this article. This project was supported by the Boston College Law School
Fund.
Citation: (2013) 59:2 McGill LJ 225 Rfrence : (2013) 59 : 2 RD McGill 225
Richard Albert 2013
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
226
Introduction
I.
II.
III.
The Functions of Constitutional Amendment Rules
A. Why Entrench Formal Amendment Rules?
B. Values in the Constitutional Text
Constitutional Values and Formal Amendment Rules
A. Creating a Constitutional Hierarchy
B. Constitutional Values and Constitutional Hierarchy
C. Constitutional Hierarchy in Formal Amendment Rules
The Authenticity of Formal Entrenchment
A. Purpose and Perception
B. Designing Constitutional Values
C. Interpreting Constitutional Values
Conclusion
227
230
231
236
239
240
244
247
257
257
264
269
280
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 227
Introduction
Formal constitutional amendment rules are largely corrective. Recog-
nizing that a deficient constitution risks building error upon error until
the only effective repair becomes revolution,1 constitutional designers en-
trench formal amendment rules that can be used to peacefully correct the
constitutions design.2 Fixing defects is therefore an essential function of
formal amendment rules. Political actors generally deploy formal
amendment rules to amend a constitutionfrom the Latin verb
emendarein order to free [it] from fault or to put [it] right.3 Yet
formal amendment rules do more than entrench a procedure for perfect-
ing apparent imperfections in the written constitution: they may also
serve the underappreciated function of expressing constitutional values.
Much of the current scholarship on constitutional amendment ex-
plores informal amendment.4 This focus, while important, has obscured
the continuing relevance of formal amendment rules. Consider formal and
1 Karl Loewenstein, Reflections on the Value of Constitutions in Our Revolutionary Age
in Arnold J Zurcher, ed, Constitutions and Constitutional Trends Since World War II
(New York: New York University Press, 1951) 191 at 215.
2 John W Burgess, Political Science and Comparative Constitutional Law I: Sovereignty
and Liberty (Boston: Ginn & Co, 1893) at 137.
3 Bryan A Garner, Modern American Usage, 3d ed (New York: Oxford University Press,
2009) at 41.
4 An informal amendment occurs when political norms change, or courts (possibly re-
sponding to political pressures) interpret or construct the constitution so as to bring it
in line with policy preferences (Tom Ginsburg & Eric A Posner, Subsconstitutional-
ism (2010) 62:6 Stan L Rev 1583 at 1600). There is vast body of scholarship on informal
amendment. See e.g. Bruce Ackerman, We the People 1: Foundations (Cambridge:
Belknap Press, 1991) at 266; Bruce Ackerman, We the People 2: Transformations (Cam-
bridge: Belknap Press, 1998) at 383420; Jeremy Webber, Reimagining Canada: Lan-
guage, Culture, Community, and the Canadian Constitution (Kingston: McGill-Queens
University Press, 1994) at 260305; David A Strauss, The Living Constitution (New
York: Oxford University Press, 2010) at 12039; Charlie Jeffery, Dimensions of Consti-
tutional Change: Germany and the United Kingdom Compared in Arthur B Gunlicks,
ed, German Public Policy and Federalism: Current Debates on Political, Legal, and So-
cial Issues (New York: Berghahn Books, 2003) 197 at 203; Stephen M Griffin, Constit-
uent Power and Constitutional Change in American Constitutionalism in Martin
Loughlin & Neil Walker, eds, The Paradox of Constitutionalism: Constituent Power and
Constitutional Form (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007) 49 at 5261; see also
SN Ray, Modern Comparative Politics: Approaches, Methods and Issues, 3d ed (Delhi:
Prentice-Hall of India, 2004) at 11731 (discussing formal and informal amendment in
comparative perspective); Brannon P Denning, Means to Amend: Theories of Constitu-
tional Change (1997) 65:1 Tenn L Rev 155 at 180209 (surveying theories of informal
amendment); Heather K Gerken, The Hydraulics of Constitutional Reform: A Skepti-
cal Response to Our Undemocratic Constitution (2007) 55:4 Drake L Rev 925 at 92933
(cataloguing recent scholarship on informal constitutional amendment); see generally
Sanford Levinson, ed, Responding to Imperfection: The Theory and Practice of Constitu-
tional Amendment (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995) (compiling essays on
constitutional change, both formal and informal) [Levinson, Responding].
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
228
informal amendment practices in the United States. Today it is difficult,5
if not virtually inconceivable,6 to gather the supermajorities needed to
formally amend the United States Constitution pursuant to Article V.7
That there have been only twenty-seven textual additions to the Constitu-
tion since 1789and of those, ten were packaged as the Bill of Rights
reveals just how rarely political actors have resorted to the constitutions
formal amendment procedures.8 Spurred by the difficulty of constitutional
change through Article V, 9 political actors have innovated alternative
methods to keep current the centuries-old constitution.10 Today, informal
amendment prevails so predominantly over formal amendment that Arti-
cle V amendments have been described as irrelevant.11 But while Article
V amendments may perhaps be irrelevant, Article V itself is not.
Like other formal amendment rules, Article V entrenches special polit-
ical commitments. We can discern from Article Vs equal suffrage clause,
5 See Barry Friedman & Scott B Smith, The Sedimentary Constitution (1998) 147:1 U
Pa L Rev 1 at 45; David E Kyvig, Arranging for Amendment: Unintended Outcomes of
Constitutional Design in David E Kyvig, ed, Unintended Consequences of Constitution-
al Amendment (Athens: Univeristy of Georgia Press, 2000) 9 at 1011.
6 See Sanford Levinson, Our Undemocratic Constitution: Where the Constitution Goes
Wrong (And How We the People Can Correct It), 2d ed (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2006) at 21; Stephen M Griffin, The Nominee is … Article V (1995) 12:2 Const
Commentary 171 at 172.
7 US Const art V:
The Congress, whenever two-thirds of both Houses shall deem it necessary,
shall propose Amendments to this Constitution, or, on the Application of the
Legislatures of two thirds of the several States, shall call a Convention for
proposing Amendments, which, in either Case, shall be valid to all Intents
and Purposes, as part of this Constitution, when ratified by the Legislatures
of three fourths of the several States, or by Conventions in three fourths
thereof, as the one or the other Mode of Ratification may be proposed by the
Congress; Provided that no Amendment which may be made prior to the
Year One thousand eight hundred and eight shall in any Manner affect the
first and fourth Clauses in the Ninth Section of the first Article; and that no
State, without its Consent, shall be deprived of its equal Suffrage in the Sen-
ate.
8 See William B Fisch, Constitutional Referendum in the United States of America
(2006) 54:4 Am J Comp L (supplement) 485 at 49091.
9 See e.g. William E Scheuerman, Constitutionalism in an Age of Speed (2002) 19:2
Const Commentary 353 at 37475; Donald S Lutz, Toward a Theory of Constitutional
Amendment (1994) 88:2 Am Pol Sci Rev 355 at 364.
10 See Adam M Samaha, Dead Hand Arguments and Constitutional Interpretation
(2008) 108:1 Colum L Rev 606 at 618.
11 See generally David A Strauss, The Irrelevance of Constitutional Amendments (2001)
114:5 Harv L Rev 1457 at 1460.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 229
as well as its reference to the importation12 and census-based taxation13
clauses, that federalism is an historically important constitutional value
in the United States. Germanys formal amendment rules similarly reflect
that states constitutional valuesspecifically the value of human dignity,
which is absolutely entrenched against formal amendment in the German
Basic Law.14 We may also look to the Canadian and South African consti-
tutions for evidence that formal amendment rules express constitutional
values. Much like the formal amendment rules in the United States Con-
stitution and the German Basic Law, the design of these rules in the Ca-
nadian and South African constitutions is more than simply corrective. As
I will show,15 their formal amendment rules entrench a constitutional hi-
erarchy that reflects a rank-ordering of constitutional values.16
In this article, I advance the scholarship on constitutional amendment
by showing that formal amendment rulesnot formal amendments, but
the rules pursuant to which formal amendments themselves are made
express constitutional values. My thesis is neither that formal amend-
ment rules always express constitutional values nor that designers neces-
sarily intend formal amendment rules to serve this function. It is instead
that formal amendment rules are one of the sites where constitutional de-
signers may express a politys constitutional values, both internally to the
persons who are nominally or actually bound by its terms, and externally
to the larger world. This article generates a research agenda for further
inquiry into the use of formal amendment rules to express values.
This is a useful contribution to the study of formal amendment be-
cause it both clarifies and complicates their study. It clarifies it by demon-
strating that formal amendment rules serve the underappreciated func-
tion of expressing constitutional values; yet it also complicates it by
stressing that it is not always clear whether the constitutional values en-
trenched in formal amendment rules express authentic or inauthentic po-
12 The Migration or Importation of such Persons as any of the States now existing shall
think proper to admit, shall not be prohibited by the Congress prior to the Year one
thousand eight hundred and eight, but a Tax or duty may be imposed on such Importa-
tion, not exceeding ten dollars for each Person (US Const, supra note 7, art I, s 9).
13 No Capitation, or other direct, Tax shall be laid, unless in Proportion to the Census or
enumeration herein before directed to be taken (ibid).
14 Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany, 1949, translated by U.S. Department of
State, arts 1(1) (the dignity of man shall be inviolable), 79(3) (absolutely entrenching
article 1(1) against formal amendment) [Basic Law].
15 See Parts IIIII, below.
16 See Constitution Act, 1982, ss 3849, being Schedule B to the Canada Act 1982 (UK),
1982, c 11 [Constitution Act, 1982]; Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996,
No 108 of 1996, s 74 [Constitution of South Africa].
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
230
litical commitments. This has important implications for constitutional
design.
I begin, in Part I, by identifying and explaining the functions scholars
have generally attributed to formal amendment rules; I show that none of
these functions fully accounts for the expressive nature of formal amend-
ment rules. In Part II, I draw from a number of national constitutions, in-
cluding the constitutions of Canada and South Africa, to illustrate how
formal amendment rules may entrench and express constitutional values
by creating a formal constitutional hierarchy. Part III confronts an ana-
lytical difficulty: the values that constitutional designers choose to en-
trench in formal amendment rules may reflect either actual or inauthen-
tic political commitments. Using the German Basic Law as a model, I ex-
plain how we may discern whether entrenched constitutional values rep-
resent authentic political commitments. I suggest that the authenticity of
the constitutional values entrenched in Germanys formal amendment
rules derives from their validation by the Constitutional Court, their cen-
trality to German political culture, and their entrenchment in the Basic
Law. I conclude with additional thoughts for deepening the comparative
study of formal amendment rules.
I. The Functions of Constitutional Amendment Rules
Few tasks in constitutional design are more important than structur-
ing formal amendment rules.17 Scholars have attributed several functions
to formal amendment rules. Scholars generally understand these rules as
managing political action and regulating constitutional change: Amend-
ing formulas set up mechanisms that endeavor to tame constitutional ac-
tors and encapsulate the relationship between the constitution and the
passage of time.18 More specifically, formal amendment rules are said to
distinguish a constitution from ordinary law, to structure the formal
amendment process, to precommit19 future political actors, and to facili-
tate improvements or corrections to the constitutional text.20 They also
heighten public awareness, check political branches, promote democracy,
17 See Sanford Levinson, Designing an Amendment Process in John Ferejohn, Jack N
Rakove & Jonathan Riley, eds, Constitutional Culture and Democratic Rule (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001) 271 at 275.
18 Xenophon Contiades & Alkmene Fotiadou, Models of Constitutional Change in Xeno-
phon Contiades, ed, Engineering Constitutional Change: A Comparative Perspective on
Europe, Canada and the USA (New York: Routledge, 2013) 417 at 431.
19 See Jon Elster, Ulysses Unbound: Studies in Rationality, Precommitment, and Con-
straints (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
20 See Part I.A, below.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 231
and pacify constitutional change.21 Formal amendment rules do indeed
serve each of these functions, as I will explain in this Part. But they
should also be understood as one of several sites where constitutional de-
signers may entrench and thereby express constitutional values. None of
the functions scholars have attributed to them adequately reflects this
expressive role.
A. Why Entrench Formal Amendment Rules?
First, as a basic matter, formal amendment rules distinguish constitu-
tional text from ordinary legislation. Whereas laws are ordinarily subject
to repeal or amendment by a simple legislative majority, a constitutional
text is often subject to a higher threshold for alteration.22 This higher
threshold could be approval by a legislative or popular supermajority, and
it sometimes requires both. 23 More demanding procedures for formal
amendment reflect both the relatively higher significance afforded to con-
stitutions over laws and the view that ordinary law is derivative of consti-
tutional law.24 However, designing formal amendment rules so as to re-
tain a constitutions distinction from ordinary law may be easier said than
done, because it requires pinpointing precisely the right level of amend-
21 Ibid.
22 See Andrs Saj, Limiting Government: An Introduction to Constitutionalism (New
York: Central European University Press, 1999) at 3940; Carl Schmitt, Constitutional
Theory, ed and translated by Jeffrey Seitzer (Durham: Duke University Press, 2008) at
7172; Edward Schneier, Crafting Constitutional Democracies: The Politics of Institu-
tional Design (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2006) at 222. Although constitutions
are generally subject to higher thresholds for repeal or formal amendment than are or-
dinary laws, it is nonetheless possible to make it feasible to repeal constitutions by sim-
ple majority vote, just as ordinary laws may themselves be entrenched against repeal
by simple majority vote. See Larry Alexander, Constitutions, Judicial Review, Moral
Rights, and Democracy: Disentangling the Issues in Grant Huscroft, ed, Expounding
the Constitution: Essays in Constitutional Theory (New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2008) 119 at 120.
23 See Jan-Erik Lane, Constitutions and Political Theory, 2d ed (Manchester: Manchester
University Press, 2011) at 41. Formal amendment rules may also be designed to deny
popular majorities the power of constitutional amendment by conferring that power ex-
clusively upon political actors. See Joel I Coln-Ros, Weak Constitutionalism: Demo-
cratic Legitimacy and the Question of Constituent Power (London, UK: Routledge, 2012)
at 4. Formal amendment rules may similarly be designed to prevent fleeting majorities
from making significant constitutional changes. See Geoffrey de Q Walker, The Rule of
Law: Foundation of Constitutional Democracy (Carlton, Austl: Melbourne University
Press, 1988) at 381.
24 See Donald S Lutz, Toward a Theory of Constitutional Amendment in Levinson, Re-
sponding, supra note 4, 237 at 240 [Lutz, Theory].
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
232
ment difficulty.25 The higher the frequency of formal amendment, the
more the constitution may seem like an ordinary law.26
Second, scholars have observed that formal amendment rules struc-
ture the process by which political actors change the text and meaning of
a constitution. Formal amendment rules provide a legal and transparent
framework within which to alter the constitution, 27 whereas informal
amendment occurs arguably pursuant to extralegal procedures.28 To call
informal amendment extralegal is not to make a claim about its legitima-
cy. As Bruce Ackerman has argued, there exist informalthough none-
theless properprocedures beyond those expressly detailed in Article V to
amend the United States Constitution.29 To describe informal amendment
procedures as extralegal and formal amendment rules as legal is
therefore only to highlight that informal amendment procedures are not
outlined in a constitutional text, in contrast to formal amendment rules,
which are entrenched within it.
25 See John R Vile, Contemporary Questions Surrounding the Constitutional Amending
Process (Westport, Conn: Praeger, 1993) at 2; Leslie Wolf-Phillips, Introduction in
Leslie Wolf-Phillips, ed, Constitutions of Modern States: Selected Texts and Commen-
tary (New York: Praeger, 1968) at xxv.
26 See Kathleen Sullivan, Constitutional Amendmentitis, online: (1995) The American
Prospect at 2223
27 See Vivien Hart, Democratic Constitution Making, online: (2003) 107 United States
Institute of Peace Special Report 1 at 4.
28 See Rosalind Dixon & Richard Holden, Constitutional Amendment Rules: The Denom-
inator Problem in Tom Ginsburg, ed, Comparative Constitutional Design (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 2012) 195 at 195. Akhil Amar has argued that Article V of
the United States Constitution does not provide the only way to formally amend the
text. His argumentthat a majority of Americans may, by referendum, amend the
Constitutionis a novel view on extralegal, yet nonetheless formal, constitutional
amendment. See Akhil Reed Amar, Philadelphia Revisited: Amending the Constitu-
tion Outside Article V (1988) 55:4 U Chicago L Rev 1043 at 1060.
29 Bruce A Ackerman, Transformative Appointments (1988) 101:6 Harv L Rev 1164 at
1179; see also sources catalogued in Levinson, Responding, supra note 4 (compiling
sources on informal amendment in both the United States and elsewhere). For critiques
of Ackermans theory of informal amendment, see e.g. James E Fleming, We the Un-
conventional American People (1998) 65:4 U Chicago L Rev 1513; Michael J Klarman,
Constitutional Fact/Constitutional Fiction: A Critique of Bruce Ackermans Theory of
Constitutional Moments (1992) 44:3 Stan L Rev 759; Larry Kramer, Whats a Consti-
tution for Anyway? Of History and Theory, Bruce Ackerman and the New Deal (1996)
46:3 Case W Res L Rev 885; Gerald N Rosenberg, The Unconventional Conventional-
ist (1999) 2:2 Green Bag (2d) 209; Frederick Schauer, Deliberating About Delibera-
tion (1992) 90:6 Mich L Rev 1187; Suzanna Sherry, The Ghost of Liberalism Past
(1992) 105:4 Harv L Rev 918; Laurence H Tribe, Taking Text and Structure Seriously:
Reflections on Free-Form Method in Constitutional Interpretation (1995) 108:6 Harv L
Rev 1221.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 233
Third, formal amendment rules precommit future political actors to
the entrenched choices of the constitutions authors. The strongest pre-
commitment device is a subject-matter restriction on formal amendment,
which constitutional designers entrench to privilege something in the con-
stitutional design by making it unamendable.30 To borrow from Sanford
Levinson, a formally unamendable constitution would reflect constitu-
tional designers inordinate confidence in their own political wisdom cou-
pled perhaps with an equally inordinate lack of confidence in successor
generations.31 Constitutional designers may also distrust political actors
and consequently create formal amendment rules to limit their future
choices.32 Lawrence Sager makes plain this connection between precom-
mitment and distrust, arguing that constitutional designers make consti-
tutions difficult to amend because [w]e trust ourselves, perhaps, but not
those who will succeed us in stewardship of our political community.33
The most important devices to foster precommitment, according to Jon
Elster, are supermajorities and delays.34
Fourth, scholars have explained that formal amendment rules offer a
way to improve the design of a constitution by correcting the faults that
time and experience reveal. Brannon Denning and John Vile have made
this point persuasively:
If the nation is to continue with a written constitution that contains
the specificity of some of the provisions of the existing document,
there will be times when, absent flagrant disregard for constitution-
al language, some amendments will be required as defects become
apparent, or changes are desired.35
Amendment procedures allow political actors to respond to the changing
political, social, and economic needs of the political community36needs
30 See Jon Elster, Constitutionalism in Eastern Europe: An Introduction (1991) 58:2 U
Chicago L Rev 447 at 471.
31 Sanford Levinson, The Political Implications of Amending Clauses (1996) 13:1 Const
Commentary 107 at 112 [Levinson, Amending Clauses].
32 See Donald J Boudreaux & A C Pritchard, Rewriting the Constitution: An Economic
Analysis of the Constitutional Amendment Process (1993) 62:1 Fordham L Rev 111 at
12324.
33 Lawrence G Sager, The Birth Logic of a Democratic Constitution in Ferejohn, Rakove
& Riley, supra note 17, 110 at 124.
34 Jon Elster, Ulysses Unbound: Studies in Rationality, Precommitment, and Constraints
(Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2000) at 104.
35 Brannon P Denning & John R Vile, The Relevance of Constitutional Amendments: A
Response to David Strauss (2002) 77:1 Tul L Rev 247 at 275.
36 See Gabriel L Negretto, Toward a Theory of Formal Constitutional Change: Mecha-
nisms of Constitutional Adaptation in Latin America in Detlef Nolte & Almut Schil-
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
234
that the governing constitution may inadequately serve, whether as a re-
sult of suboptimal constitutional design or new social circumstances.37
Formal amendment rules therefore operate against the backdrop of hu-
man error and exist to redress shortcomings in the design of the constitu-
tion itself.38
Formal amendment rules also heighten public awareness and deliber-
ation. They invite political actors to debate and negotiate publicly about
what they believe best serves the common interest, and they ensure that
society acts on well-founded and stable expectations about the conse-
quences of amending a constitution.39 Formal amendment rules, which
commonly require some form of supermajority action, promote careful
consideration of the issues … by forcing those in favor of a particular
proposition to persuade a larger segment of the population.40 Therefore,
for Donald Lutz, formal amendment rules are means [t]o arrive at the
best possible decisions in pursuit of the common good under a condition of
popular sovereignty.41 The product of this public deliberationa formal
amendment inscribed in the text of a constitutionin turn makes possible
the publication and reinforcement of constitutional norms. Formal
amendment, write Denning and Vile, undeniably changes the Constitu-
tion in one significant respect: it adds language to the Constitution.42 As
a result, [t]he publicity accompanying the change may, in fact, increase
public expectations that the change will be honored by the other branches
[of government], raising the costs of evasion or under-enforcement.43
Sixth, formal amendment rules also act as a check between branches
of government. They give political actors a mechanism to revise the in-
formal constitutional amendments entrenched by courts of last resort in
ling-Vacaflor, eds, New Constitutionalism in Latin America: Promises and Practices
(Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 2012) 51 at 52.
37 See Raymond Ku, Consensus of the Governed: The Legitimacy of Constitutional
Change (1995) 64:2 Fordham L Rev 535 at 542.
38 See Bjrn Erik Rasch & Roger D Congleton, Amendment Procedures and Constitu-
tional Stability in Roger D Congleton & Birgitta Swedenborg, eds, Democratic Consti-
tutional Design and Public Policy: Analysis and Evidence (Cambridge, Mass: MIT
Press, 2006) 319 at 326.
39 Ibid at 327.
40 Ku, supra note 37 at 571.
41 Lutz, Theory, supra note 24 at 23940.
42 Denning & Vile, supra note 35 at 279.
43 Ibid.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 235
the course of constitutional interpretation.44 Rosalind Dixon observes that
formal amendment rules allow political actors both to move courts toward
new constitutional interpretations and to trump courts constitutional
judgments.45 Interestingly, however, formal amendment rules may also
have the opposite effect depending on their rigidity. The more exacting
the process of consummating a formal amendment, the more insulated
from reversal by amendment the judiciarys constitutional judgments be-
come; conversely, the less burdensome the formal amendment process,
the greater the power held by political actors to shape and reshape consti-
tutional meaning.46 The durability of judicial judgments is therefore di-
rectly proportional to the rigidity of formal amendment.
Scholars have also pointed to the democracy-promoting function of
formal amendment rules. The right to amend a constitution is, above all,
a right to democratic choice. Perhaps most prominently on this point, Jed
Rubenfeld has argued that [t]he very principle that gives the [US] Con-
stitution legitimate authoritythe principle of self-government over
timerequires that a nation be able to reject any part of a constitution
whose commitments are no longer the peoples own.47 Rubenfeld con-
cludes that [t]hus written constitutionalism requires a process not only of
popular constitution-writing, but also of popular constitution-rewriting.48
In addition to promoting the majoritarian bases of democracy, formal
amendment rules may also promote the substantive dimensions of democ-
racy, namely its counter-majoritarian and minority-protecting purposes.
As Roger Congleton explains, formal amendment rules support the rule
of law insofar as constitutional stability is increased and/or minority pro-
tections are enhanced.49
Finally, scholars also interpret formal amendment rules as making
possible sweeping but non-violent political transformations. This pacifying
function is perhaps best articulated by Walter Dellinger, who posits that
44 See Andre Lajoie & Henry Quillinan, Emerging Constitutional Norms: Continuous
Judicial Amendment of the ConstitutionThe Proportionality Test as a Moving Tar-
get (1992) 55:1 L & Contemp Probs 285 at 285.
45 Rosalind Dixon, Constitutional Amendment Rules: A Comparative Perspective in
Tom Ginsburg & Rosalind Dixon, eds, Comparative Constitutional Law (Cheltenham,
UK: Edward Elgar, 2011) 96 at 98.
46 Arend Lijphart, Patterns of Democracy: Government Forms and Performance in Thirty-
Six Countries (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999) at 22830.
47 Jed Rubenfeld, Freedom and Time: A Theory of Constitutional Self-Government (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 2001) at 174.
48 Ibid.
49 Roger D Congleton, Perfecting Parliament: Constitutional Reform, Liberalism, and the
Rise of Western Democracy (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011) at 287.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
236
the Article V amendment process in the United States Constitution rep-
resents a domestication of the right to revolution.50 Entrenching the rules
of formal amendment in a constitutional text provides a roadmap for ef-
fecting constitutional changes that range from modest to major, without
having to write an entirely new constitution, resort to irregular methods
of constitutional renewal, or take up arms. In the United States at the
Federal Convention of 1787, George Mason echoed this very point, recog-
nizing that constitutional amendments would be inevitable but that it
will be better to provide for them, in an easy, regular and Constitutional
way than to trust to chance and violence.51 This function fosters a higher
probability of constitutionally continuousrather than constitutionally
discontinuous52change under formal amendment rules. As Dixon ex-
plains, formal amendment rules increase the chances that such change
will occur (at least more or less) within existing constitutional frame-
works, rather than via processes of whole-scale constitutional revision or
overthrow.53
B. Values in the Constitutional Text
Formal amendment rules certainly do serve each of the eight functions
that scholars have attributed to them. But they also have an additional
function: to express constitutional values. Although some have suggested
or recognized this claim, none has yet to fully develop the thesis that for-
mal amendment rules either expressly declare or more subtly signal con-
stitutional values. Samuel Finer, Vernon Bogdanor, and Bernard Rudden
make this point most directly when they state in their important compar-
ative study of constitutions that formal amendment rules may express
basic values.54 But these scholars mention this only in passing, without
further development, and only in reference to unamendable constitutional
provisions. As I will show in the pages to follow, unamendable provisions
50 Walter Dellinger, The Legitimacy of Constitutional Change: Rethinking the Amend-
ment Process (1983) 97:2 Harv L Rev 386 at 431.
51 Max Farrand, ed, The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, revised ed (New Ha-
ven: Yale University Press, 1966) vol 1 at 203.
52 Constitutional change is continuous where it occurs under the authority of the existing
constitution and does not result in a new regime; in contrast, constitutional change is
discontinuous where it does not occur under this authority. See Peter Suber, The Para-
dox of Self-Amendment: A Study of Logic, Law, Omnipotence, and Change (New York:
Peter Lang, 1990) at 18.
53 Dixon, supra note 45 at 97.
54 SE Finer, Vernon Bogdanor & Bernard Rudden, Comparing Constitutions (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1995) at 13.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 237
are not the only formal amendment rules that may express constitutional
values.55
Stephen Holmes and Cass Sunstein have made a similar observation.
In their constitutional design scholarship advising new democracies how
to structure their formal amendment rules, they explore both the tension
between liberalism and democracy in designing formal amendment rules
and the consequences for democracy of adopting stringent formal rules.
Holmes and Sunstein argue that the procedures used to formally amend a
constitution [shed] light on the variety of theories underlying different
liberal democracies.56 They conclude that formal amendment rules [help]
us identify the broad norms and basic commitments behind the constitu-
tional fine print.57
Others have suggested more indirectly that formal amendment rules
may be used to express constitutional values. Levinson, for example, has
observed that Article V of the United States Constitution varies the diffi-
culty of the amendment process with the perceived importance of given is-
sues, referring specifically to the equal suffrage clause.58 For their part,
Denning and Vile have developed the notion of [t]he [p]ublicity [f]unction
of [w]ritten [a]mendments.59 But their focus has been on formal amend-
ments themselves, not on the rules for their entrenchment. Dixon has
noted that various countries have established various distinct tracks for
constitutional amendment that vary according to the subject-matter of a
proposed amendment, with specific reference to India and South Africa.60
But these scholars have yet to explain and illustrate how formal amend-
ment rules may actually express constitutional values.
Constitutional scholars have long argued, however, that constitutions
may serve an expressive function. Some constitutions are written to re-
flect the meta-constitutional norms that bind a constitutional community
and distinguish this particular community from others. Mark Tushnet ex-
plains that constitutions, both in their entrenched institutional arrange-
ments and in the doctrines that emerge from their interpretation, are
ways in which a nation goes about defining itself.61 As Tom Ginsburg has
55 See Part II.C, below.
56 Stephen Holmes & Cass R Sunstein, The Politics of Constitutional Revision in Eastern
Europe in Levinson, Responding, supra note 4, 275 at 27879.
57 Ibid at 279.
58 Levinson, Amending Clauses, supra note 28 at 122.
59 Denning & Vile, supra note 35 at 279.
60 Dixon, supra note 45 at 103.
61 Mark Tushnet, Weak Courts, Strong Rights: Judicial Review and Social Welfare Rights
in Comparative Constitutional Law (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008) at 12.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
238
observed, [i]n some polities, constitutions reflect and sometimes even
create a shared consciousness, and so overcome regional or ethnic divi-
sions.62 He adds that [t]he symbolic or expressive function of constitu-
tions emphasizes the particularity of constitution-making. It is We the
People that come together, and so the constitution embodies our nation in
a distinct and local way different from other polities.63 Constitutions may
therefore express values with the aspirational or functional purposes of
self-definition and nation building.64
Constitutions may also express values without exerting any immedi-
ate or perceptible legal effect. Sunstein has observed that constitutional
provisions make statements about a nations objectives and aspirations,
and that some may attribute significance to such statements even if the
consequences of those statements are unclear.65 He cites as an example an
anti-discrimination norm upon which a society might insist for expres-
sive reasons even if [that society] does not know whether the law actually
helps members of minority groups. He continues:
The point bears on the cultural role of law, adjudication, and even of
Constitutional Court decisions. When the Court makes a decision, it
is often taken to be speaking on behalf of the nations basic princi-
ples and commitments. This is a matter of importance quite apart
from consequences, conventionally understood.66
Expression, then, is distinct from prohibition or authorization.
The values of a constitution reflect what Gary Jacobsohn calls the con-
stitutions identity.67 To discern a constitutions identity, the first though
not the only place to look is its text.68 The writtenness69 of a constitution
62 Tom Ginsburg, Written Constitutions and the Administrative State: On the Constitu-
tional Character of Administrative Law in Susan Rose-Ackerman & Peter L Lindseth,
eds, Comparative Administrative Law (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2010) 117 at 118.
63 Ibid.
64 But see Sanford Levinson, The Constitution in American Civil Religion [1979] Sup Ct
Rev 123 (questioning whether the United States Constitution can serve as a source of
national unity: [i]t is ironic that a culture which has experienced a centuries-long mel-
ancholy, long-withdrawing roar from religious faith can believe so blithely in the con-
tinuing reality of a collectivity of citizens organized around a constitutional faith at
15051).
65 Cass R Sunstein, On the Expressive Function of Law (1996) 5:1 E Eur Const Rev 66
at 67.
66 Ibid.
67 Gary Jeffrey Jacobsohn, Constitutional Identity (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University
Press, 2010) at 348.
68 See ibid.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 239
serves in part to codify a societys fundamental ideals and structures;70
but their codification and attendant interpretation need not remain static:
they may change over time.71 This is to be expected since, as Mary Ann
Glendon has explained in her comparative study of abortion and divorce,
law, in addition to all the other things it does, tells stories about the cul-
ture that helped to shape it and which it in turn helps to shape: stories
about who we are, where we came from, and where we are going.72 These
stories, which we may broadly understand as representing the values held
within a community, seem to have a powerful influence not only on how
legal norms are invented and applied within that system, but on how facts
are perceived and translated into the language and concepts of the law.73
To deconstruct the metaphor, the values expressed by and in law filter
throughout the legal system.
II. Constitutional Values and Formal Amendment Rules
Constitutional values are the foundation of any constitutional regime.
They help us rank the regimes rules, principles, and institutional ar-
rangements relative to each other in a hierarchical order.74 They inform
the choices political actors make and how judges interpret the constitu-
tion, and they may also reflect how a regime defines itself, both internally
and externally. Constitutional values are the equivalent of a trump card
in constitutional adjudication: where a constitutional value is set against
a non-constitutional value, the constitutional value will prevail in a con-
flict against the non-constitutional value of efficiency. Constitutional val-
ues may moreover be both preservative and aspirational: they may seek
to preserve something about the structure of the statefor instance, fed-
eralism or republicanismjust as they may aspire to an ideal that is im-
69 See Andrew B Coan, The Irrelevance of Writtenness in Constitutional Interpretation
(2010) 158:4 U Pa L Rev 1025.
70 See Thomas C Grey, The Constitution as Scripture (1984) 37:1 Stan L Rev 1 at 16.
71 For a discussion of the evolution of the United States Constitution as a symbol since its
adoption, see Max Lerner, Constitution and Court as Symbols (1937) 46:8 Yale LJ
1290 at 12941305.
72 Mary Ann Glendon, Abortion and Divorce in Western Law (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard
University Press, 1987) at 8.
73 Ibid.
74 See Walter F Murphy, Slaughter-House, Civil Rights, and Limits on Constitutional
Change (1987) 32 Am J Juris 1 at 22.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
240
perfectly attainable but nonetheless deemed worth pursuingfor exam-
ple, liberty or equality.75
A. Creating a Constitutional Hierarchy
Constitutional values are contestable, however, for at least two rea-
sons. First, the content of constitutional values may be contested because
they are commonly stated at a high level of generality. This invites com-
peting interpretations of such values as justice, fairness, or the rule of
law.76 Second, the actual identity of constitutional values may be contest-
ed because it is unclear how we are to identify which values do, or should,
prevail in a constitutional community where those values are not express-
ly identified in a constitutional text.77 Were it even possible to agree on a
set of values, the challenge of mediating among them would remain.
Where one value collides with another, the governing one may be difficult
to predict without reference to an authoritative predetermined hierarchy
of values, whether formally or informally entrenched.
Constitutional theory can help create a hierarchy of constitutional
values. Consider the United States Constitution, a document whose text
nowhere expressly declares which values hold greater significance than
others. Given the Constitutions indeterminate text, how are we to identi-
fy the values that have precedence within it? Walter Murphy has devel-
oped one theory, among several possibilities, to rank-order the constitu-
tional values in the United States Constitution. He begins by acknowledg-
ing the difficulty of ranking its values:78 At the root of the problem is that
the American Constitutionlike all such charterstries to foster not one
or two but a whole cluster of values.79 But Murphy posits that in light of
the evolution of the American polity since its founding, there is one value
that is most fundamental among the Constitutions substantive values:
human dignity.80 With human dignity identified as the US Constitutions
75 Cass Sunstein borrows from Lawrence Lessig in his discussion of preservative and
transformative constitutions. See Cass R Sunstein, Designing Democracy: What Consti-
tutions Do (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001) at 6768.
76 See Richard A Primus, When Should Original Meanings Matter? (2008) 107:2 Mich L
Rev 165 at 17273.
77 Ibid at 17374.
78 See Walter F Murphy, The Art of Constitutional Interpretation: A Preliminary Show-
ing in M Judd Harmon, ed, Essays on the Constitution of the United States (Port Wash-
ington: Kennikat Press, 1978) 130 at 147.
79 Ibid.
80 Ibid at 156.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 241
core substantive value, we can then proceed to rank order the others by
inquiring which are more or less consonant with serving human dignity.81
In addition to constitutional theory, constitutional interpretation can
also help shape a hierarchy of values. Where the constitutional text does
not entrench a formal hierarchy, courts may generate an informal one by
way of constitutional interpretation, as constitutional interpretation inev-
itably compels judges to balance or reconcile competing claims. For exam-
ple, a court could interpret a constitutional provision as being immune
from legal challenges alleging a violation of a protected right or liberty,
thereby conferring upon that provision a special status, perhaps as a re-
sult of historical circumstance (this is what the Supreme Court of Canada
has done with respect to section 93 of the Constitution Act, 1867).82 Alter-
natively, a court could, through interpretation, create a hierarchy by ad-
judicating a dispute that requires the court to balance competing rights
that collide.83 When two or more rights and interests intersect, courts
must determine which prevails over the other given the particular facts of
81 See Walter F Murphy, An Ordering of Constitutional Values (1980) 53:2 S Cal L Rev
703 at 754.
82 See Adler v Ontario, [1996] 3 SCR 609 at 64041, 140 DLR (4th) 385 [Adler]. Adler con-
cerned the modern application of a founding arrangement requiring Quebec to protect
the rights of its Protestant religious minority and Ontario to protect those of its Roman
Catholic religious minority. The arrangement, which was entrenched in section 93 of
Canadas Constitution Act, 1867 ((UK), 30 & 31 Vict, c 3, reprinted in RSC 1985, App II,
No 5 [Constitution Act, 1867]), required Quebec to fund Protestant religious schools and
Ontario to fund Roman Catholic religious schools. Three groups of plaintiffs challenged
the constitutionality of section 93. They argued that it violated the constitutional free-
doms of conscience and religion as well as the right to equalityentrenched in the more
recent Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms (Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982,
supra note 16)insofar as it mandated the funding of religious schools for these reli-
gious minorities to the exclusion of mandatory funding for other religious faiths. In
reaching its decision, the Supreme Court explained that [s]ection 93 is the product of
an historical compromise which was a crucial step along the road leading to Confedera-
tion and that [w]ithout this solemn pact, this cardinal term of Union, there would
have been no Confederation (Adler, supra note 78 at 640). The Court interpreted sec-
tion 93 as effectively immune from constitutional challenges based on the freedoms of
conscience and religion as well as on the right to equality: [a]s a child born of historical
exigency, s. 93 does not represent a guarantee of fundamental freedoms (ibid). Adler
therefore exempts section 93 from constitutional challenge. It would be inaccurate to
describe section 93 as trumping all other constitutional provisions, however; it is more
accurate to regard section 93 having a status equal to the rights entrenched in the
Charter.
83 All constitutional courts engage in this form of balancingwhich is commonly referred
to as a proportionality analysiswhether the items to be balanced are rights, liberties,
constitutional arrangements or structures, national values, or otherwise. See e.g. David
M Beatty, The Ultimate Rule of Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004) (ob-
serving and theorizing the ubiquity of proportionality analysis in constitutional courts).
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
242
the case. As courts resolve more cases like these, an informal constitu-
tional hierarchy emerges among those rights and interests.
For example, in the absence of a textually explicit hierarchy of values
in the United States Constitution, US constitutional law has created an
informal hierarchy of values through the Supreme Courts constitutional
interpretation. Over the course of American constitutional history, the
Supreme Court of the United States has made judgments about which
rights, rules, principles, and structures are worthy of greater protection
than others. Whether the context has been balancing one right against
another, assessing the constitutionality of state action, or simply inter-
preting the constitutional text, the Supreme Court has effectively rank-
ordered US constitutional provisions along a scale of relative importance.
The Courts informal constitutional hierarchy is flexible, subject to revi-
sion by subsequent interpretation, and not entrenched against amend-
ment; it is the product of dynamic interpretation, not of fixed constitu-
tional design at the time of the Constitutions drafting. But it is neverthe-
less an authoritative declaration of values. In this way, the difficulty of
using Article V to formally amend the US Constitution is mitigated by the
Supreme Courts ability to informally order and reorder the hierarchy of
constitutional values.
The US Supreme Courts informal hierarchy is reflected in its tripar-
tite sequence of scrutiny applied to evaluating the constitutionality of
state action: rational basis, intermediate, and strict scrutiny. As Richard
Fallon has observed, these scrutiny tests emerged as a result of the Su-
preme Courts solidifying commitment to a jurisprudential distinction be-
tween ordinary rights and liberties, which the government could regulate
upon the showing of any rational justification, and more fundamental or
preferred liberties entitled to more stringent judicial protection.84 The
Court has traditionally reserved strict scrutinythe most stringent level
of skepticism shown to a government decisionfor state action that is al-
leged to compromise, among others, racial equality,85 political rights,86 and
fundamental
level of scrutiny
84 Richard H Fallon, Jr., Strict Judicial Scrutiny (2007) 54:5 UCLA L Rev 1267 at 1285.
85 See e.g. Adarand Constructors v Pena, 515 US 200, 115 S Ct 2097 (1995) (holding that
freedoms. 87 The second highest
all racial classifications must be subject to strict scrutiny).
86 See e.g. Citizens United v Federal Election Commission, 558 US 310, 130 S Ct 876(2010)
(right to political speech); Tashjian v Republican Party of Connecticut, 479 US 208, 107
S Ct 544 (1986) (right to association); Kramer v Union Free School District No 15, 395
US 621, 89 S Ct 1886 (1969) (right to vote).
87 See e.g. Saenz v Roe, 526 US 489, 119 S Ct 1518 (1999) (right to travel); Church of the
Lukumi Babalu Aye v Hialeah (City of), 508 US 520, 113 S Ct 2217 (1993) (freedom of
religion).
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 243
intermediate scrutinyhas been applied to a category of rights and sta-
tuses that includes gender discrimination,88 illegitimacy,89 and commercial
speech.90 The US Supreme Court applies the lowest level of scrutiny
rational basisto whatever does not fall within either strict or intermedi-
ate scrutiny.91 The Courts scrutiny standards therefore express the rela-
tive standing of constitutional values by creating an informal hierarchy
ordering rights and status along an ascending scale of importance.92
In addition to constitutional theory and constitutional law, constitu-
tional design offers another way to establish a hierarchy of values. In con-
trast to the informal hierarchy that develops through judicial interpreta-
tion, constitutional design can create a more formal hierarchy in three
principal ways. First, constitutional designers may express values in the
constitutions preamble. As Levinson explains, preambles sometimes con-
vey a commitment to some scheme of universal values.93 Preambles of-
ten invoke such lofty ideals as justice,94 liberty,95 and democracy.96 Alt-
hough these values are often stated a high level of generality that could
render them content-less, recent scholarship shows that rights and prin-
88 See United States v Virginia, 518 US 515, 116 S Ct 2264 (1996); Craig v Boren, 429 US
190, 97 S Ct 451 (1976).
89 See Clark v Jeter, 486 US 456, 108 S Ct 1910 (1988); Lalli v Lalli, 439 US 259, 99 S Ct
518 (1978).
90 See Central Hudson Gas & Electric Corp v Public Service Commission of New York, 447
US 557, 100 S Ct 2343 (1980); Virginia State Board of Pharmacy v Virginia Citizens
Consumer Council, Inc, 425 US 748, 96 S Ct 1817 (1976).
91 See e.g. New York City Transit Authority v Beazer, 440 US 568, 99 S Ct 1355 (1979);
Railway Express Agency v New York, 336 US 106, 69 S Ct 463 (1949). But note that
there are effectively two levels of rational basis review, one deferential and the other
more rigorous. See Kenji Yoshino, The New Equal Protection (2011) 124:3 Harv L Rev
747 at 75960.
92 See Calvin Massey, The New Formalism: Requiem for Tiered Scrutiny? (2004) 6:5 U
Pa J Const L 945 at 99294.
93 Sanford Levinson, Do Constitutions Have a Point?: Reflections on Parchment Barriers
and Preambles (2011) 28:1 Social Philosophy & Policy 150 at 177.
94 See e.g. Constitution of the Republic of Angola, 2008, preamble; Constitution of the Re-
public of Paraguay, 1992, No 63 of 1992, translated by Maria de Carmen Gress, pream-
ble; Constitution of the Bolivarian Republic of Venezuela, 1999, translated by Ministry
of Communication and Information of the Bolivarian Republic of Venezuela, preamble.
95 See e.g. Constitution of the Republic of Cuba, 1976, translated by Anna I Vellv Torras,
preamble [Constitution of Cuba]; Constitution de la Rpublique franaise 1958, JO, 5
October 1958 9151, preamble; Constitution of Morocco, 2011, translated by Jefri J
Ruchti, preamble.
96 See e.g. Constitution fdrale de la Confdration suisse, 1998, preamble; Constitution of
the Republic of Uzbekistan, 1992, preamble; Constitution of the Republic of Zambia,
1991, No 1 of 1991, as amended by Constitution of the Republic of Zambia Act, No 18 of
1996, preamble [Constitution of Zambia].
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
244
ciples listed in a constitutions preamble are increasingly interpreted as
justiciable.97
Second, designers may choose to express values elsewhere in the text
of the constitution. For instance, the South African constitution opens, af-
ter its preamble, with a declaration that the state is founded on a series of
values including human dignity, equality, non-racialism, non-sexism, the
rule of law, and multi-party democratic government.98 Spain likewise ex-
pressly states values in the text of its constitution outside the preamble,
entrenching the statement that Spain is hereby established as a social
and democratic State, subject to the rule of law, which advocates freedom,
justice, equality and political pluralism as highest values of its legal sys-
tem.99 Kazakhstan also follows this model, stating after the preamble of
its constitution that [t]he Republic of Kazakhstan proclaims itself a dem-
ocratic, secular, legal and social state whose supreme values are the indi-
vidual, his life, rights and freedoms.100
B. Constitutional Values and Constitutional Hierarchy
Constitutional designers may also entrench and therefore express con-
stitutional values in a third way: in their design of formal amendment
rules. When constitutional designers entrench these rules, they may be
electing more than a formal amendment procedure; they may be choosing
deliberately to identify special political commitments. Formal amendment
rules should consequently be seen as a third site where constitutional de-
signers may establish and express a formal hierarchy of values. I use the
word may to stress that formal amendment rules are only sometimes in-
tended to express values. The point is therefore a modest one. It is not
that all formal amendment rules always convey constitutional values; in-
stead, formal amendment rules are one of many sites within a constitu-
tional order for entrenching values and communicating them both inter-
nally (within the constitutional community) and externally (beyond its
borders). While all constitutional provisions express some form of both
substantive and procedural values, insofar as they are the product of ne-
gotiation and often partisan political contests about how to govern a con-
stitutional community, I am focusing on a relatively narrow dimension of
97 See Liav Orgad, The Preamble in Constitutional Interpretation (2010) 8:4 Interna-
tional Journal of Constitutional Law 714 at 738.
98 See Constitution of South Africa, supra note 16, s 1.
99 Constitution of Spain, 1978, as amended to 1992, translated by Comparative Constitu-
tions Project, s 1.
100 Constitution of the Republic of Kazakhstan, 1995, as amended to No 403-IV of 2011,
translated by the Constitutional Council of the Republic of Kazakhstan, art 1(1).
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 245
constitutional design: the values expressed by the text of formal amend-
ment rules.
With this in mind, consider three provisionsA, B, and Cin a hypo-
thetical written federal constitution currently in draft, prior to its ratifica-
tion, at a constitutional convention today. Assume that the constitutional
designers create three different thresholds for formal amendment and
that they make A subject to formal amendment by the lowest of the three
formal thresholds: simple majority agreement in both houses of the na-
tional legislature and simple majority approval from the sub-national leg-
islatures. The constitutional designers choose to require a higher thresh-
old to formally amend B: supermajority in both houses and supermajority
approval from the sub-national legislatures. The designers then subject C
to the highest amendment threshold: supermajority agreement in both
houses of the national legislature, supermajority approval from the sub-
national legislatures, and a national referendum ratified by majority vote.
We can draw four interdependent conclusions about the constitutional
designers choices with respect to A, B, and C in this hypothetical consti-
tutional design. First, we can conclude that the designers understand A,
B, and C as qualitatively different from one another in some respect. Sec-
ond, we can deduce that the designers wish to find a mechanism by which
to validate these perceived qualitative differences. Third, we can recog-
nize that the designers wish to convey their validation of these known dif-
ferences by entrenching them somewhere in the constitutional text. More
specifically, fourth, we can conclude that the designers have identified the
rules of formal amendment as one place within the constitution in which
they can validate, by way of escalating entrenchment, these known differ-
ences among A, B, and C.
This deliberate choice to vary the level of difficulty for formally
amending A, B, and C could reflect one of three conclusions. These conclu-
sions are not mutually exclusive and are closely related; yet it is im-
portant to distinguish them analytically, even though they may overlap.
First, the choice to make one constitutional provision subject to a higher
formal amendment threshold could represent a political bargain entered
into by the constitutional designers for the sake of ratifying an otherwise
unratifiable constitution. This possibility is illustrated by the equal suf-
frage clause in the United States Constitution,101 which requires a higher
amendment threshold for changing a states voting power in the Senate
than is required for amending anything else.102 The clause was a consti-
101 See US Const, supra note 7, art V.
102 Another example of an absolutely necessary compromise provision in the US Constitu-
tion is the temporary entrenchment of the slave trade, as Ozan Varol explains in his
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
246
tutional essential 103 to the adoption of the US Constitution; smaller
states worried that without its protection, the larger, more populous
states would overrun their interests.104 Madison explained that the clause
was probably meant as a palladium to the residuary sovereignty of the
States, implied and secured by that principle of representation in one
branch of the Legislature; and was probably insisted on by the States par-
ticularly attached to that equality.105 Entrenching this heightened formal
amendment protection was therefore a condition precedent to the Un-
ion.106
The different thresholds for formally amending A, B, and C could also
reflect the concern that future generations of political actors will be
tempted to act in their self-interest by seeking to amend certain power-
conferring constitutional provisions. The Honduran constitution illus-
trates such a concern. That constitutions designers thought it necessary,
given the nations history, to entrench presidential term limits against
formal amendment;107 accordingly, the constitutional text designates the
presidential term limit provision as unamendable.108 The durability and
legitimacy of this rule were recently tested when then-President Manuel
Zelaya proposed a national referendum on amending the term limit pro-
hibition.109
study of temporary constitutions. See Ozan O Varol, Temporary Constitutions 102 Cal
L Rev [forthcoming in 2014] at 4042.
103 Douglas G Smith, An Analysis of Two Federal Structures: The Articles of Confedera-
tion and the Constitution (1997) 34:1 San Diego L Rev 249 at 322.
104 Roger Sherman argued that each State ought to be able to protect itself: otherwise a
few large States will rule the rest (Farrand, ed, supra note 51 at 196). Sherman also
suggested that [t]he smaller States would never agree to the plan on any other princi-
ple (than an equality of suffrage in this branch[)] (ibid at 201).
105 James Madison, The Federalist No. 43, in Jacob E Cooke, ed, The Federalist (Mid-
dletown: Wesleyan University Press, 1961) 288 at 296.
106 After several debates on the matter, the equal suffrage clause was adopted without op-
position. See Farrand, ed, supra note 51 at 50509.
107 See Teresa Stanton Collett, Judicial Independence and Accountability in an Age of Un-
constitutional Constitutional Amendments (2010) 41:2 Loy U Chi LJ 327 at 34546.
108 See Constitution of the Republic of Honduras, 1982, No 131 of 1982, arts 239 (establish-
ing one-term rule), 374 (entrenching article 239 against formal amendment).
109 For a discussion and analysis of this episode, see e.g. Frank M Walsh, The Honduran
Constitution is Not a Suicide Pact: The Legality of Honduran President Manuel Ze-
layas Removal (2010) 38:2 Ga J Intl & Comp L 339; Doug Cassel, Honduras: Coup
dEtat in Constitutional Clothing?Revision, online: (2009) 13:9 ASIL Insights
duras Forbes (28 September 2009), online: Forbes
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 247
The choice to vary the level of amendment difficulty among A, B, and
C could also reflect a third conclusion, which is the one that will occupy
the remainder of this article. The different thresholds for formally amend-
ing A, B, and C could reflect a considered judgment about their relative
importance. On this theory, to require a more demanding formal amend-
ment threshold for C than for B, and likewise for B than for A, is to de-
clare that C is the most important provision among the three, followed by
B, and finally by A. What results from this constitutional design, then, is
a formal constitutional hierarchy that identifies the principles, rules,
rights, or structures that constitutional designers wish to privilege.110
C. Constitutional Hierarchy in Formal Amendment Rules
Constitutional values may therefore be ordered in a constitutional hi-
erarchy in the design of formal constitutional amendment rules. In this
section, I will demonstrate how constitutional hierarchies may emerge
from four different designs of these rules: (1) an escalating structure of
formal amendment rules, as exhibited by the Canadian, South African,
Ghanaian, Nigerian, and Indian constitutions; (2) subject-matter re-
strictions, as demonstrated by the Cuban, Afghan, and Brazilian constitu-
tions; (3) an escalating structure of formal amendment rules alongside
subject-matter restrictions, with reference to the Ukrainian constitution;
and (4) a non-escalating structure of formal amendment rules alongside
subject-matter restrictions, as seen in the Cameroonian and Portuguese
constitutions. I note at the outset that we should not attribute the inten-
tion to express a relative ordering of constitutional importance to all con-
stitutional hierarchies. As I have stressed above, the entrenchment of a
formal constitutional hierarchy can reflect one or more motivations,
namely political bargaining, a defense against self-dealing, and the ex-
pression of values; it often reflects some combination of these three.
Consider first the Canadian Constitution Act, 1982. Its text creates
five escalating tiers of entrenchment with different procedures to formally
amend the constitution, each imposing higher and still higher thresholds
Honduran President Is Ousted In Coup New York Times (29 June 2009), online: New
York Times
110 I am grateful to Tom Ginsburg for the point that measuring amendment difficulty is
challenging. For example, it is difficult to assess whether achieving a majority in a na-
tional referendum is harder than achieving a supermajority in a bicameral legislature.
But when escalating amendment thresholds are cumulative rather than simply dissimi-
lar, one can posit that each increasing threshold will be harder to achieve than the pre-
vious threshold.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
248
for altering certain constitutional provisions.111 The first is known as the
general amendment procedure, under which a formal amendment re-
quires resolutions from both the House of Commons and the Senate as
well as resolutions from at least two-thirds of the provinces representing
at least half of the total provincial population.112 This procedure is the Ca-
nadian constitutions default rule for formal amendment: unless otherwise
specified, all formal amendments must be achieved using the general
amendment procedure. The constitution also specifies that certain
itemsnamely provincial representation in the Senate, senatorial powers
and elections, and the creation of new provincesare amendable only
through the general amendment procedure.113
The second amendment procedure is more stringent than the general
procedure, requiring unanimous agreement among both houses of Par-
liament and each provincial legislature.114 It applies to five expressly des-
ignated matters: (1) the monarchy and its representation in Canada; (2)
provincial representation in the House of Commons; (3) the use of English
and French, subject to the bilateral/multilateral procedure discussed be-
low; (4) the composition of the Supreme Court of Canada; and (5) the for-
mal amendment procedures themselves.115 The third bilateral/multilateral
111 See Constitution Act, 1982, supra note 16, ss 3849. Some scholars interpret Canadas
formal amendment rules as consisting of seven different procedures. See e.g. James
Ross Hurley, Amending Canadas Constitution: History, Processes, Problems and Pro-
spects (Ottawa: Canada Communication Group, 1996) at 69; Tsvi Kahana, Canada in
Dawn Oliver & Carlo Fusaro, eds, How Constitutions Change: A Comparative Study
(Portland: Hart Publishing, 2011) 9 at 25. But as Hurley concedes, [o]pinions may
vary, however, on the precise number of procedures (Hurley, supra note 111 at 69). I
agree with Peter Hoggs interpretation that there are five formal amendment proce-
dures. See Peter W Hogg, Formal Amendment of the Constitution of Canada (1992)
55:1 Law & Contemp Probs 253 at 257.
112 See Constitution Act, 1982, supra note 16, s 38(1). A province may opt out of a constitu-
tional amendment passed using the general procedure in certain circumstances. See
ibid, s 38(3).
113 Ibid, s 42(1):
An amendment to the Constitution of Canada in relation to the following
matters may be made only in accordance with subsection 38(1): (a) the prin-
ciple of proportionate representation of the provinces in the House of Com-
mons prescribed by the Constitution of Canada; (b) the powers of the Senate
and the method of selecting Senators; (c) the number of members by which a
province is entitled to be represented in the Senate and the residence qualifi-
cations of Senators; (d) subject to paragraph 41(d), the Supreme Court of
Canada; (e) the extension of existing provinces into the territories; and
(f) notwithstanding any other law or practice, the establishment of new prov-
inces.
114 Ibid, s 41.
115 Ibid.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 249
procedure, in contrast, is less exacting than the general formula. Under
this procedure, resolutions from both houses of Parliament and from the
legislature(s) of an affected province are necessary for amendments relat-
ing to the alteration of boundaries between provinces, the use of English
or French within a province, or any other matter applying to some but not
all provinces.116
The fourth and fifth proceduresthe federal unilateral procedure and
its provincial unilateral equivalentare even less exacting than the bilat-
eral/multilateral procedure. The federal unilateral procedure authorizes
the national Parliament to formally amend the Constitution by passing a
law.117 This procedure applies only to matters relating to the executive
government or the houses of Parliament, and excludes those matters con-
cerning executive government and the national legislature that are ex-
pressly keyed to higher amendment thresholds.118 The provincial unilat-
eral procedure authorizes provincial legislatures to formally amend their
own constitutions by passing a law.119 This procedure applies to all pro-
vincial matters except those specifically assigned higher amendment
thresholds.120
It is possible to conceptualize these amendment procedures along an
ascending scale of difficulty. Each procedure adds an additional hurdle be-
fore political actors may consummate a formal amendment. (For the mo-
ment, let us set aside the provincial unilateral amendment procedure be-
cause it applies only to amendments of a provincial, not the national, con-
stitution, although we should understand a provincial constitution to in-
corporate parts of the written and unwritten constitution of Canada, and
116 Ibid, s 43:
An amendment to the Constitution of Canada in relation to any provision
that applies to one or more, but not all, provinces, including (a) any altera-
tion to boundaries between provinces, and (b) any amendment to any provi-
sion that relates to the use of the English or the French language within a
province, may be made by proclamation issued by the Governor General un-
der the Great Seal of Canada only where so authorized by resolutions of the
Senate and House of Commons and of the legislative assembly of each prov-
ince to which the amendment applies.
117 Subject to sections 41 and 42, Parliament may exclusively make laws amending the
Constitution of Canada in relation to the executive government of Canada or the Senate
and House of Commons (ibid, s 44).
118 Ibid. In a current project related to the recent Senate Reference, I am developing the
argument that Canadas escalating design of formal amendment rules are more compli-
cating than clarifying.
119 Subject to section 41, the legislature of each province may exclusively make laws
amending the constitution of the province (ibid, s 45).
120 Ibid.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
250
likewise the written and unwritten constitution of Canada incorporates
within it parts or all of each of the provincial constitutions.) The proce-
dures along each threshold are cumulative; each one incorporates the
lower threshold in some manner. The lowest level of amendmentthe
federal unilateral procedurerequires simple majorities in each of the
two houses of Parliament. 121 The next highest thresholdthe bilat-
eral/multilateral proceduredemands both the requirements of the fed-
eral unilateral procedure and a resolution from the affected province(s).122
The general formula is the third highest threshold; it requires both the
agreement of the two houses of Parliament and the consent of seven of the
ten provinces representing at least fifty per cent of the provincial popula-
tion.123 Finally, the unanimity requirement is the hardest one of all, re-
quiring both houses of Parliament and each of the ten provinces to
agree.124
These escalating tiers of formal entrenchment may signal constitu-
tional designers intent to match the level of formal amendment difficulty
to the significance of the role the designated provision occupies, either
functionally in the constitutional regime or symbolically in the constitu-
tional text.125 For Stephen Scott, the multiple formal amendment proce-
dures should be seen as standing in a hierarchy, so that the former
stands to the latter as the more difficult to the less difficultwith Scott
referring to the more comprehensive and less comprehensive procedures,
respectively.126 Peter Hogg observes that the highest level of formal en-
trenchment in the Canadian constitutionthe unanimity procedure
applies to the most important matters, what he calls specially en-
trenched provisions that are have national significance: The five listed
topics are specially entrenched because they are deemed to be matters of
national significance which should not be altered over the objection of
even one province.127 Walter Dellinger makes a similar observation, not-
ing that Canadas formal amendment rules provide special protection to
121 Ibid, s 44.
122 Ibid, s 43.
123 Ibid, s 38(1). Territorial population does not appear to count toward national popula-
tion. See ibid, s 38(2).
124 Ibid, s 41.
125 I am currently completing a paper in which I explore the origins and evolution of Cana-
das formal amendment rules. This paper will show that although the design of Cana-
das escalating amendment rules were intended to express values along a constitutional
hierarchy, their design was also constrained by constitutional history in important
ways that have yet to be explored.
126 Stephen A Scott, Pussycat, Pussycat or Patriation and New Constitutional Amend-
ment Processes (1982) 20 UWO L Rev 247 at 304.
127 Peter W Hogg, Constitutional Law of Canada, 5th ed (Toronto: Carswell, 2012) at 425.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 251
certain very fundamental matters, distinguishing the highest amend-
ment threshold from the lower ones.128 Escalating amendment thresholds
may therefore be deployed, as they have been in Canada, to make it hard-
er to amend special constitutional provisions, though they may also be the
result of a political bargain or a defense against self-interest, as discussed
above.
The South African constitutions escalating tiers of formal amendment
are similar to those in Canadas Constitution Act, 1982. The South African
constitution entrenches three amendment procedures which, like the for-
mal amendment thresholds in the Canadian constitution, may each be
used to amend a limited universe of constitutional provisions. Take the
most demanding formal amendment procedure. It requires approval by
three-quarters of South Africas National Assembly and two-thirds of its
National Council of Provinces, and it must be used for any formal
amendment to the constitutions declaration of values and to this amend-
ment formula.129 The mid-level formula calls for a lower thresholdtwo-
thirds approval in the National Assembly and two-thirds approval in the
National Council of Provincesand applies to any formal amendment to
the Bill of Rights, the National Council of Provinces, and provincial mat-
ters.130 The least demanding formula requires only two-thirds approval in
the National Assembly and is to be used for formal amendments to all
other constitutional matters.131 What results from these escalating thresh-
olds of formal amendment is a constitutional hierarchy, with South Afri-
cas stated constitutional values and the formal amendment procedures at
the top, the Bill of Rights and provincial matters in the middle, and all
other constitutional provisions below.
A similar hierarchy is observable in other constitutions that entrench
escalating thresholds of formal amendment. In the Ghanaian constitution,
formally amending certain provisions, for example the constitutions pro-
128 Walter Dellinger, The Amending Process in Canada and the United States: A Com-
parative Perspective (1982) 45:4 Law & Contemp Probs 283 at 300.
129 Constitution of South Africa, supra note 16, s 74(1). The constitutions statement of con-
stitutional values proclaims that
[t]he Republic of South Africa is one, sovereign, democratic state founded on
the following values: (a) Human dignity, the achievement of equality and the
advancement of human rights and freedoms. (b) Non-racialism and non-
sexism. (c) Supremacy of the constitution and the rule of law. (d) Universal
adult suffrage, a national common voters roll, regular elections and a multi-
party system of democratic government, to ensure accountability, respon-
siveness and openness (ibid, s 1).
130 Ibid, s 74(2).
131 Ibid, s 74(3).
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
252
tections for fundamental rights and freedoms, 132 requires a very high
threshold of agreement: there must be a proposal in Parliament and con-
sultation with the Council of State, followed by a referendum with at least
forty per cent popular participation and three-quarters approval, ratifica-
tion by Parliament, and assent from the President.133 In contrast, another
group of constitutional provisions, for instance the provision authorizing
the President to appoint the Chief of Defense Staff of the Armed Forces,134
may be amended by a moderately less onerous process requiring a pro-
posal in Parliament, consultation with the Council of State, two succes-
sive votes of two-thirds approval in Parliament, and the Presidents as-
sent.135 The Ghanaian constitution thus has a two-tier hierarchy that sets
fundamental rights and freedoms apart from other provisions.
132 Constitution of the Republic of Ghana, 1992, arts 1233 [Ghanaian Constitution].
133 Ibid, art 290. Fundamental rights and freedoms are considered entrenched in the
Ghanaian Constitution. The following procedures govern the formal amendment of en-
trenched provisions:
(2) A bill for the amendment of an entrenched provision shall, before Par-
liament proceeds to consider it, be referred by the Speaker to the Coun-
cil of State for its advice and the Council of State shall render advice on
the bill after thirty days after receiving it.
The bill shall be published in the Gazette but shall not be introduced in-
to Parliament until the expiry of six months after the publication in
the Gazette under this clause.
(3)
(4) After the bill has been read the first time in Parliament it shall not be
proceeded with further unless it has been submitted to a referendum
held throughout Ghana and at least forty percent of the persons entitled
to vote, voted at the referendum and at least seventy-five percent of the
persons who voted cast their votes in favour of the passing of the bill.
(5) Where the bill is approved at the referendum, Parliament shall pass it.
(6) Where a bill for the amendment of an entrenched provision has been
passed by Parliament in accordance with this article, the President
shall assent to it (ibid, arts 290(2)(6)).
134 Ibid, art 212(1).
135 Ibid, art 291. The following procedures govern the formal amendment of non-
entrenched provisions:
(1) A bill to amend a provision of this Constitution which is not an en-
trenched provision shall not be introduced into Parliament unless
(a) it has been published twice in the Gazette with the second publica-
tion being made at least three months after the first; and
(b) at least ten days have passed after the second publication.
(2) The Speaker shall, after the first reading of the bill in Parliament, refer
it to the Council of State for consideration and advice and the Council of
State shall render advice on the bill within thirty days after receiving it.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 253
Likewise, under the Nigerian constitution, there is a difference in
thresholds for formally amending different provisions: the Nigerian con-
stitution has a similar two-tier hierarchy that results from its escalating
model of formal amendment. At the higher threshold, a formal amend-
ment requires four-fifths approval in both houses of the national legisla-
ture as well as two-thirds approval from all sub-national legislatures. This
threshold applies to provisions concerning fundamental rights, the crea-
tion of new sub-national units, adjustments to territorial boundaries, and
the formal amendment rules themselves.136 Other constitutional provi-
sions may be formally amended with a lower threshold requiring two-
thirds approval in both houses of the national legislature and two-thirds
approval among sub-national legislatures.137
The Indian constitution also entrenches two amendment thresholds.
The higher threshold applies exclusively to specifically designated provi-
sions, while the lower threshold applies to all others. The lower threshold
requires either house of the national legislature to propose an amend-
ment, each house to pass it by a supermajority, and the President to as-
sent to it.138 All constitutional provisions are subject to this rule of formal
(3) Where Parliament approves the bill, it may only be presented to the
President for his assent if it was approved at the second and third read-
ings of it in Parliament by the votes of at least two thirds of all the
members of Parliament.
(4) Where the bill has been passed in accordance with this article, the Pres-
ident shall assent to it (ibid).
136 Constitution of the Federal Republic of Nigeria, 1999, No 27 of 1999, s 9(3):
An Act of the National Assembly for the purpose of altering the provisions of
this section, section 8 or Chapter IV of this Constitution shall not be passed
by either House of the National Assembly unless the proposal is approved by
the votes of not less than four-fifths majority of all the members of each
House, and also approved by resolution of the Houses of Assembly of not less
than two-thirds of all the States.
137 Ibid, s 9(2):
An Act of the National Assembly for the alteration of this Constitution, not
being an Act to which section 8 of this Constitution applies, shall not be
passed in either House of the National Assembly unless the proposal is sup-
ported by the votes of not less than two-thirds majority of all the members of
that House and approved by resolution of the Houses of Assembly of not less
than two-thirds of all the States.
138 See Constitution of the Sovereign Democratic Republic of India, 1950, art 368(2):
An amendment of this Constitution may be initiated only by the introduction
of a Bill for the purpose in either House of Parliament, and when the Bill is
passed in each House by a majority of the total membership of that House
and by a majority of not less than two-thirds of the members of that House
present and voting, it shall be presented to the President for his assent and
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
254
amendment unless they concern the formal amendment rules themselves,
the presidential electoral college, Union courts, federalism, or the relative
powers of the national and sub-national governments. Where an amend-
ment relates to these subjects, the Indian constitution requires an addi-
tional voting procedure prior to the Presidents assent: at least half of the
sub-national legislatures must ratify the amendment.139 Just as the Indi-
an constitution suggests through its entrenchment of formal amendment
rules that certain provisions may be more highly valued or more political-
ly salient than others, so do the Canadian, South African, and Nigerian
constitutions.
We can likewise discern a constitutional hierarchy in subject-matter
restrictions on formal amendment rules. When a constitutional text dis-
tinguishes one provision from another by expressly designating one of
them as impervious to the formal amendment rules that apply to the oth-
er, one possible message both conveyed and perceived is that one of the
two provisions is more highly valued. The degree to which a constitutional
provision is insulated from formal amendment and from the unpredicta-
bility of constitutional politics is in this case a proxy for preference. The
stricter its entrenchment, the higher the constitutional worth of a given
provision. Absolute entrenchment against formal amendment is thus the
strongest statement of a provisions value.140
To illustrate the point, consider a few examples of these subject-
matter restrictions. The Cuban constitution absolutely entrenches social-
ism against formal amendment. The text states that socialism is irrevo-
(a) Article 54, Article 55, Article 73, Article 162 or Article 241, or
(b) Chapter IV of Part V, Chapter V of Part VI, or Chapter I of Part XI, or
(c) any of the Lists in the Seventh Schedule, or
(d) the representation of States in Parliament, or
(e) the provisions of this Article,
upon such assent being given to the Bill, the Constitution shall stand
amended in accordance with the terms of the Bill:
Provided that if such amendment seeks to make any change in
the amendment shall also require to be ratified by the Legislatures of not less
than one-half of the States specified in Parts A and B of the First Schedule by
resolutions to that effect passed by those Legislatures before the Bill making
provision for such amendment is presented to the President for assent.
139 Ibid.
140 See Miriam Galston, Theocracy in America: Should Core First Amendment Values be
Permanent? (2009) 37:1 Hastings Const LQ 65 at 115.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 255
cable, and Cuba will never go back to capitalism.141 For Afghanistan, the
similarly situated value is Islam: the Afghan constitution declares that
[t]he principles of adherence to the tenets of the Holy religion of Islam as
well as Islamic Republicanism shall not be amended.142 And in Brazil,
federalism occupies the privileged position that socialism and religion oc-
cupy in Cuba and Afghanistan, respectively, insofar as its constitutional
text states that [n]o proposed constitutional amendment shall be consid-
ered that is aimed at abolishing … the federalist form of the National
Government. 143 These content restrictions on the operation of formal
amendment rules tell us just how much socialism, religion, and federal-
ism matter in Cuba, Afghanistan, and Brazil. Constitutional designers re-
garded these principles as so important as to disable the formal amend-
ment rules against them altogether.
A constitutional hierarchy can also emerge concurrently from the
combination of formal amendment rules and subject-matter restrictions.
Consider the Ukrainian constitution, a text that entrenches subject-
matter restrictions alongside escalating tiers of formal amendment. The
Ukrainian constitutions designers set apart three items from others
human rights and freedoms, national independence, and territorial integ-
rityby designating them as formally unamendable.144 Visually, we can
place these unamendable provisions at the summit of the constitutional
hierarchy. At the intermediate level of the hierarchy of importance, we
can place the Ukrainian constitutions statement of general principles, its
rules for elections and referenda, and the formal amendment rules them-
selves, for which the constitution requires a proposal by either the Presi-
dent or two-thirds of the national legislature, adoption again by a two-
thirds vote in the national legislature, and ratification via national refer-
endum.145 Finally, the remaining constitutional provisions sit at the low-
141 Constitution of the Republic of Cuba 1976, Codification of 2003, translated by Anna I
Vellv Torras & William S Hein & Co, Inc, s 3.
142 Constitution of the Islamic Republic of Afghanistan, 2004, translated by Comparative
Constitutions Project, art 149 [Constitution of Afghanistan].
143 Constitution of the Federative Republic of Brazil, 1988, translated by Comparative Con-
stitutions Project, art 60(4)(1).
144 See Constitution of Ukraine, 1996 ([t]he Constitution of Ukraine shall not be amended,
if the amendments foresee the abolition or restriction of human and citizens rights and
freedoms, or if they are aimed toward the liquidation of the independence or violation of
the territorial indivisibility of Ukraine, art 157).
145 Ibid, art 156:
A draft law on introducing amendments to Chapter IGeneral Principles,
Chapter IIIElections. Referendum, and Chapter XIIIIntroducing
Amendments to the Constitution of Ukraine, is submitted to the Verkhovna
Rada of Ukraine by the President of Ukraine, or by no less than two-thirds of
the constitutional composition of the Verkhovna Rada of Ukraine, and on the
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
256
est level of Ukraines constitutional hierarchy, for which formal amend-
ment is possible by the lower of the two amendment thresholds: proposal
by either the President or one-third of the national legislature, adoption
by a majority of the national legislature, followed by a subsequent two-
thirds vote in the national legislature.146
A hierarchy of values likewise emerges when a constitutional text
combines a non-escalating structure of formal amendment alongside sub-
ject-matter restrictions. For example, the Portuguese constitution en-
trenches content restrictions alongside a single procedure for formal
amendment. The result is a two-tier constitutional hierarchy pursuant to
which most provisions are subject to the constitutions single amendment
formula, which requires two-thirds approval from the national legisla-
ture.147 The more valued provisions are designated as unamendable and
are therefore immune from this procedure. Consider also the Came-
roonian constitution, which entrenches general formal amendment proce-
dures applicable to all of the constitutional provisions except four princi-
ples expressly designed as formally unamendable:148 republicanism, na-
condition that it is adopted by no less than two-thirds of the constitutional
composition of the Verkhovna Rada of Ukraine, and is approved by an All-
Ukrainian referendum designated by the President of Ukraine.
146 Ibid, art 155:
A draft law on introducing amendments to the Constitution of Ukraine, with
the exception of Chapter IGeneral Principles, Chapter IIIElections.
Referendum, and Chapter XIIIIntroducing Amendments to the Constitu-
tion of Ukraine, previously adopted by the majority of the constitutional
composition of the Verkhovna Rada of Ukraine is deemed to be adopted, if at
the next regular session of the Verkhovna Rada of Ukraine, no less than two-
thirds of the constitutional composition of the Verkhovna Rada of Ukraine
have voted in favour thereof.
147 Constitution of the Portuguese Republic, 1976 ([c]hanges in the Constitution shall be
approved by a majority of two-thirds of the members of the Assembly present, art
286(2)).
148 See ibid, art 63:
(1) Amendments to the Constitution may be proposed either by the Presi-
dent of the Republic or by Parliament.
(2) Any proposed amendment made by a member of Parliament shall be
signed by at least one-third of the members of either House.
(3) Parliament shall meet in congress when called upon to examine a draft
or proposed amendment. The amendment shall be adopted by an abso-
lute majority of the members of Parliament. The President of the Re-
public may request a second reading; in which case the amendment
shall be adopted by a two-third majority of the members of Parliament.
(4) The President of the Republic may decide to submit any bill to amend
the Constitution to a referendum; in which case the amendment shall be
adopted by a simple majority of the votes cast.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 257
tional unity, territorial integrity, and democracy.149 Cameroons hierarchy
of constitutional values therefore consists of two tiers: the subject-matter
restrictions are on top, and the freely formally amendable provisions are
on the bottom.
III. The Authenticity of Formal Entrenchment
The values that constitutional designers choose to entrench in formal
amendment rules may reflect either actual or inauthentic political com-
mitments. Where constitutional designers entrench values in order to ob-
scure contrary or ignoble political commitments, the disjunction between
the constitutional text and political reality becomes problematic, both for
the study of constitutional design and more immediately for those to
whom the constitution applies. But to the extent that entrenched values
accurately represent the intent or aspiration of constitutional designers,
perception and reality mutually reinforce each other in the constitutional
texts declaration of values. In this Part, I will illustrate how the purpose
and perception of constitutions and formal amendment rules may diverge.
I will also demonstrate how we can evaluate the authenticity of the con-
stitutional values entrenched in formal amendment rules. As will become
evident, the task is not an easy one, as it requires inquiry into text, law,
and culture. My subject will be the German Basic Law, though the Cana-
dian constitution could serve just as well.150
A. Purpose and Perception
Where constitutional designers entrench values in the constitutional
text, we may consider these values authentic if the designers intended
them to guide successor political and judicial actors in legislative and ex-
ecutive action and in judicial interpretation. On the other hand, where de-
149 Constitution of the United Republic of Cameroon, 1972 ([n]o procedure for the amend-
ment of the Constitution affecting the republican form, unity and territorial integrity of
the State and the democratic principles which govern the Republic shall be accepted,
art 64).
150 In a current project, I am doing just that. I am deconstructing and evaluating the de-
sign of formal amendment rules in Canada. I will build on the work of Canadian schol-
ars who have suggested that Canadas escalating formal amendment rules reflect spe-
cial political commitments. See Hurley, supra note 111; Jacques-Yvan Morin & Jos
Woehrling, Les constitutions du Canada et du Qubec: du rgime franais nos jours, t
12, 2d ed (Montreal: ditions Thmis, 1994); Benot Pelletier, La modification consti-
tutionnelle au Canada (Scarborough: Carswell, 1996); Benot Pelletier, Les modalits
de la modification de la Constitution du Canada (1999) 33 RJT 1; Peter Oliver, Cana-
da, Quebec, and Constitutional Amendment (1999) 49:4 UTLJ 519; Jos Woerhling,
Les aspects juridiques de la redfinition du statut politique et constitutionnel du Qu-
bec (19911992) 7:1 RQDI 12.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
258
signers entrench values but neither have emotional vulnerability to them
nor intend those values to influence successor actors,151 we may presume
that those entrenched values are inauthentic. This presumption may be
rebutted with evidence that successor political and judicial actors have
subsequently adopted these entrenched values as binding or guiding their
conduct. The authenticity of entrenched values, however, is neither im-
mediately nor entirely clear from a constitutional text.
That written constitutions sometimes exhibit a disjunction between
purpose and perception is a common critique of the study of formal consti-
tutions.152 As David Law and Mila Versteeg have conceded in their own
work on formal constitutions, [s]ome may object that formal constitutions
are not worth studying because what is on paper does not necessarily
translate into practice.153 We need not look further than the Kremlins
1936 Constitution of the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics to see just
151 See Samuel Scheffler, Equality and Tradition: Questions of Value in Moral and Politi-
cal Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 2010) at 29.
152 See e.g. George C Guins, Towards an Understanding of Soviet Law (1955) 7:1 Soviet
Studies 14 at 1823 (explaining why one cannot understand Soviet law by reading the
Soviet Constitution); AE Dick Howard, The Essence of Constitutionalism in Kenneth
W Thompson & Rett R Ludwikowski, eds, Constitutionalism and Human Rights: Amer-
ica, Poland, and France (London: University Press of America, 1991) 3 (describing some
constitutions as worthless scraps of papers at 4); Counterinsurgency and Constitu-
tional Design, Note, (2008) 121:6 Harv L Rev 1622:
A faade constitution can declare aspirational principles and adopt power
structures for government, but such provisions and principles are ineffective
and potentially delegitimized because they are not followed in practice. Many
African constitutions, for example, were not tailored to their social context
and were either ignored or manipulated, thereby undermining constitution-
alism and the rule of law (ibid at 1632 ×.).
See generally Linda Camp Keith, Constitutional Provisions for Individual Human
Rights (19771996): Are They More Than Mere Window Dressing? (2002) 55:1 Politi-
cal Research Quarterly 111 (finding some, though not clearly conclusive, statistical evi-
dence that certain constitutional provisions sometimes matter to the behaviour of states
with respect to human rights). The study of formal constitutions is nonetheless im-
portant. As Beau Breslin has argued, the constitutional text as a unique collection of
words, aspirations, objectives, and fundamental law is worthy of scholarly attention
(Beau Breslin, From Words to Worlds: Exploring Constitutional Functionality (Balti-
more: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2009) at 89).
153 David S Law & Mila Versteeg, The Evolution and Ideology of Global Constitutional-
ism (2011) 99:5 Cal L Rev 1163 at 1169. Law and Versteeg rebut this criticism, conced-
ing that although [s]ometimes, constitutions neither constrain nor even describe the
actual operation of the state, these are the very reasons we should study them: first,
[t]o recognize that some constitutions are shams merely begs a host of further ques-
tions, none of which can be tackled without a systematic understanding of what the
world’s constitutions actually say and, second, [i]t is one thing to observe that formal
or large-C constitutions can diverge from actual or small-c constitutional practice; it is
another thing to know when and in what ways they diverge (ibid ×.).
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 259
how widely political practice may diverge from the constitutional text.154
For political theorist Benjamin Barber, the Soviet constitution was merely
a smokescreen: although it appeared from its words to be the worlds
most effusively rights-oriented constitution in an unprecedented fortress
of human liberty, the truth was plainly the opposite.155
This disjunction between purpose and perception is what Jan-Erik
Lane calls the gulf between the formal written constitution and the real
political constitution.156 Lane acknowledges that no regime successfully
fulfills the entirety of its written constitutional commitments, but that
some do better than others: No state lives one hundred per cent in ac-
cordance with its written documents.157 It is the size of the gulf between
the codified constitution and the political constitution that matters in as-
sessing how well or poorly a regime measures up to its formally en-
trenched commitments. An authoritarian state would likely exhibit much
greater dissonance between its written and political constitutions than a
democratic one, which is more likely to aspire to harmonize the two. As
Lane writes:
[I]n dictatorships and authoritarian states there is typically a tre-
mendous distance between the formal constitution and the real con-
stitution. Often such states enact a constitutional document which
has no connection whatsoever to institutional practices in the coun-
try. It is only a camouflage constitution.158
David Law explains that camouflage constitutions serve a number of ulte-
rior motives, including gaining credibility in the international community
or securing foreign investment.159
The problem, posits William Andrews, is that over the course of the
nineteenth and twentieth centuries, written constitutionalism became
154 See Constitution (Fundamental Law) of the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics, 1936.
155 Benjamin R Barber, Constitutional RightsDemocratic Instrument or Democratic
Obstacle? in Robert A Licht, ed, The Framers and Fundamental Rights (Washington,
DC: AEI Press, 1992) 23 at 30.
156 Lane, supra note 23 at 45.
157 Ibid.
158 Ibid.
159 David S Law, Constitutions in Peter Cane & Herbert M Kritzer, eds, The Oxford
Handbook of Empirical Legal Research (New York: Oxford University Press, 2010) 376
at 380. Qianfan Zhang has discussed the related reasons why China continues to main-
tain a camouflage constitution. See Qianfan Zhang, A Constitution Without Constitu-
tionalism? The Paths of Constitutional Development in China (2010) 8:4 International
Journal of Constitutional Law 950 at 95256.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
260
synonymous with democracy.160 Documentary Constitutions, he writes,
have come to be identified with constitutionalism.161 Authoritarian re-
gimes have taken advantage of this positive identification, exploiting
what Giovanni Sartori calls the favorable emotive properties of the word
constitution.162 Sartori describes the phenomenon in greater detail:
[T]he political exploitation and manipulation of language takes ad-
vantage of the fact that the emotive properties of a word surviveat
times for a surprisingly long timedespite the fact that what the
word denotes, i.e., the thing, comes to be a completely different
thing.163
Equating constitutions with constitutionalism was and remains problem-
atic because authoritarian regimes take advantage of that association to
hide behind a strategically drafted democracy-embracing constitutional
text that appears consistent with constitutionalism but really is only a fa-
ade. As Andrews explains, many regimes in the world today have Con-
stitutions without constitutionalism. Tyrants, whether individual or col-
lective, find that Constitutions are convenient screens behind which they
can dissimulate their despotism.164
Formal amendment rules in constitutional texts are equally suscepti-
ble to authoritarian commandeering. Insofar as formal amendment rules
reflect the usually unstated value of sovereignty,165 the rules are a profit-
able and inexpensive site where authoritarian regimes may express inau-
thentic values while securing for themselves the goodwill that may come
from their public, even if dishonest, association with democratic ideals.
Examples abound of suspicious constitutional entrenchment. When we
read the Russian Federations constitution, which entrenches an escalat-
ing scale of formal amendment that makes it comparatively more difficult
160 William G Andrews, Constitutions and Constitutionalism, 2d ed (New York: D Van
Norstand Company, 1963) at 22.
161 Ibid.
162 Giovanni Sartori, Constitutionalism: A Preliminary Discussion (1962) 56:4 Am Polit
Sci Rev 853 at 855.
163 Ibid.
164 Andrews, supra note 160 at 2223. For a useful, though perhaps controversial, illustra-
tion of how authoritarian states behave undemocratically despite purporting to respect
democracy, see Kenneth Roth, Depots Masquerading as Democrats in World Report
(2008), online: Human Rights Watch
165 See e.g. Claude Klein & Andrs Saj, Constitution-Making: Process and Substance in
Michel Rosenfeld & Andrs Saj, eds, The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Constitu-
tional Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012) 419 at 438; Michel Troper, Sover-
eignty in Rosenfeld & Saj, ibid, 350 at 36365.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 261
to amend civil and political rights,166 we should therefore ask whether this
special entrenchment actually expresses an authentic political commit-
ment to protect these rights. This question should also arise when we
read the Zambian constitution, which does the same with respect to its
own fundamental rights and freedoms.167 Similar questions may be asked
of the formal amendment rules in Bangladesh,168 Belarus,169 Ethiopia,170
or Singapore,171 among many others.172 The best answer is to always take
a skeptical posture to any special or absolute entrenchment of constitu-
tional values, and to evaluate whether the formally entrenched value
aligns in reality with constitutional practice.
One of the weaknesses of entrenching values in formal amendment
rules therefore doubles as the biggest weakness of written constitutions:
their democratic commitments on parchment sometimes conceal undemo-
cratic practices in reality.173 Walter Murphy cautions us against supposing
that constitutions necessarily bind political actors, because [t]o think
that words can constrain power seems foolish.174 Constitutional commit-
ments, after all, are but words on paperand to borrow again from Law
and Versteeg, sometimes, constitutions lie.175 Law and Versteeg have
shown that constitutions often promise more than they deliver, not only
for illegitimate reasons associated with authoritarian regimes that find
shelter under the cover of constitutionalism, but also for legitimate budg-
etary limitations that, despite good intentions, make it difficult to honour
166 Constitution of the Russian Federation, 1993, translated by Comparative Constitutions
Project, arts 13437.
167 Constitution of Zambia, supra note 96, s 79.
168 See Constitution of the Peoples Republic of Bangladesh, 1972, s 142.
169 See Constitution of the Republic of Belarus, 1994, ss 14649.
170 See Constitution of the Federal Democratic Republic of Ethiopia, No 1 of 1995, arts 104
05.
171 See Constitution of the Republic of Singapore, 1963, No 1493 of 1963 (1999 Rev Ed), art
5.
172 See e.g. Political Constitution of the Republic of Guatemala, 1985, as amended by Legis-
lative Accord No 18-93 of 1993, translated by Luis Francisco Valle Velasco, arts 27780;
Iraqi Constitution, 2005, art 126; Constitution of the Republic of the Union of Myanmar,
2008, arts 43336; Constitution of the Republic of Rwanda, No 42 of 2003, art 193; Con-
stitution of Sierra Leone, 1991, No 6 of 1991, art 108.
173 For contemporary illustrations, see David Landau, Abusive Constitutionalism (2013)
47 UC Davis L Rev [forthcoming].
174 Walter Murphy, Constitutions, Constitutionalism, and Democracy in Douglas Green-
berg et al, eds, Constitutionalism and Democracy: Transitions in the Contemporary
World (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993) 3 at 7.
175 David S Law & Mila Versteeg, Sham Constitutions (2013) 101:4 Cal L Rev 863 at 865
[Law & Versteeg, Sham Constitutions].
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
262
constitutionally entrenched socio-economic rights.176 The former, however,
are examples of sham constitutions because they knowingly and pur-
posely fail to live up to the commitments they have publicly undertak-
en.177
Some sham constitutions proclaim a commitment to human rights in
their formal amendment rules, yet political actors do not conform their
conduct to those commitments; such commitments therefore reflect an in-
authentic expression of values. Although in these states, subject-matter
restrictions purport to prohibit formal amendments to the human rights
protections inscribed in their constitutions, political practice belies the
textual respect for human rights. For instance, Afghanistan, Algeria, the
Central African Republic, and Chad all entrench subject-matter re-
strictions on formal amendment to fundamental rights and freedoms,
purporting to express the states commitment to these rights.178 But these
four constitutional regimes appear in Law and Versteegs hall of shame,
a list of the twenty-five worst sham constitutions that combine far-
176 Ibid at 868.
177 Ibid at 865.
178 See Constitution of Afghanistan, supra note 142, art 149:
The principles of adherence to the tenets of the Holy religion of Islam as well
as Islamic Republicanism shall not be amended. Amending fundamental
rights of the people shall be permitted only to improve them. Amending other
Articles of this Constitution, with due respect to new experiences and re-
quirements of the time, as well as provisions of Articles 67 and 1 Hundred 46
of this Constitution, shall become effective with the proposal of the President
and approval of the majority of National Assembly members;
Constitution of Algeria, 1996, No 96-438, art 178:
No constitutional revision may infringe on:
1. the Republican character of the State.
2. the democratic order based on plural parties.
3. Islam, as the religion of the State.
4. Arabic, as the national and official language.
5. the fundamental freedoms, on the rights of man and the citizen.
6. the integrity and unity of the national territory.
See also Constitution of the Central African Republic, 2004, translated by Jefri J Ruchti
([e]xpressly excluded from revision are: the republican and secular form of the State;
the number and duration of presidential mandates; the conditions for eligibility; the in-
compatibilities to the functions of Head of State; the fundamental rights of the citizen,
art 108); Constitution of the Republic of Chad, 1996, as amended to 2005, translated by
Jefri J Ruchti ([n]o procedure of revision may be engaged or pursued when it infringes:
the integrity of the territory, the independence, or the national unity; the republican
form of the State, the principle of the separation of powers and secularity; the freedoms
and fundamental rights of citizens; the policy [of] pluralism, art 223).
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 263
reaching promises with relative little respect for rights in practice.179
These constitutional regimes benefit from the goodwill of the uninformed,
who read the regimes respective constitutional texts believing that the
texts reflect reality.
Another more recent example of an inauthentic expression of constitu-
tional values is evident in the constitution of the Democratic Republic of the
Congo.180 Drafted by members of the current presidents then-transitional
government,181 the constitutions formal amendment rules designate sev-
eral mattersincluding republicanism, universal suffrage, and repre-
sentative governmentas formally unamendable, 182 and they prohibit
formal amendments that have the effect of diminishing human rights and
liberties.183 We can suspect, however, that the Congos governing political
class is not truly committed to these values,184 given the states low rank-
ing as an authoritarian regime in the Economists Democracy Index.185
That the governing class in the Democratic Republic of the Congo does not
appear to conform its conduct to the values entrenched in the constitu-
tions formal amendment rules suggests that it exploits the entrenchment
of these values largely for public relations purposes.
Truly democratic and sham constitutions fall on the extremes of the
constitutional spectrum. Both are relatively easy to recognize, particularly
when compared to the vast number of middle-range regimes whose com-
bination of constitutional text, institutional structures, political practices,
179 Law & Versteeg, Sham Contsitutions, supra note 175 at 899.
180 Constitution of the Democratic Republic of Congo, 2006, as consolidated to No 11/002 of
2011, translated by Jefri J Ruchti [Constitution of DRC].
181 DR Congo Backs New Constitution (12 January 2006), online: BBC News Service
182 See Constitution of DRC, supra note 180, art 220.
183 Ibid.
184 The current president warned at the time of the referendum held to ratify the new con-
stitution that rejecting it would have catastrophic consequences for peace in the coun-
try. See A Ray of Hope in the Heart of Africa (19 December 2005), online: The Econo-
mist
whelming supermajority because of citizens wish to make peace, to rebuild, and to
combat their own war wariness rather than their broad popular involvement in the
process of constitution-making. See James Thuo Gathii, Popular Authorship and Con-
stitution Making: Comparing and Contrasting the DRC and Kenya (2008) 49:4 Wm &
Mary L Rev 1109 at 112324.
185 See The Economist Intelligence Unit, Democracy Index 2012: Democracy at a Stand-
still (2013) at 8, online: The Economist
Democratic Republic of the Congo ranks 159 out of the worlds 167 countries on such
democratic measures as electoral process and pluralism, the functioning of govern-
ment, and civil liberties (ibid).
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
264
and civil society make it difficult to categorize their constitutions as clear-
ly democratic or clearly sham. For these regimes, the inquiry into the au-
thenticity of the values expressed in their formal amendment rules re-
quires an analysis of the constitutional text, an evaluation of its interpre-
tation by political actors, and an assessment of whether the entrenched
constitutional values align with the political culture. This inquiry cannot
yield a quick answer, but it is likely to produce the correct one.
B. Designing Constitutional Values
Few would contend that a constitutional text can on its own transform
a political culture indisposed to the rules the text enshrines and averse to
the values it proclaims. Despite the problematic divergence between con-
stitutional entrenchment and political commitment, the expressive func-
tion of written constitutionsand of formal amendment rules more specif-
icallymay nevertheless hold promise for helping to align constitutional
text with political practice. As James Madison suggested, although [i]t
may be thought that all paper barriers against the power of the communi-
ty are too weak to be worthy of attention, the rules and values en-
trenched in a written constitution may have a tendency to impress some
degree of respect for them, to establish the public opinion in their favor,
and rouse the attention of the whole community.186 Perhaps the strength
of this tendency may be measured only retrospectively, since the future
success of a constitution cannot reliably be known at its drafting. The best
hypothesis is that constitutions and the values entrenched within their
formal amendment rules are only as strong as their commitment to cul-
turally specific and socially relevant values.187
The expressive function of constitutional amendment rules has im-
portant implications for constitutional interpretation. The task of inter-
preting entrenched values need not commit us to a particular technique of
interpretation, be it originalism, living constitutionalism, or another
method. As I have written elsewhere, formal amendment rules may be
both preservative and transformational: they may seek to preserve some-
thing thought to be distinctive about, or fundamentally constitutive of, the
state and its people,188 or they may repudiate the past by setting the
state on a new course.189 We may therefore interpret an entrenched value
from an originalist perspective consistent with preservative entrench-
186 US, Annals of Cong, vol 1, at 455 (8 June 1979).
187 HWO Okoth-Ogendo, Constitutions Without Constitutionalism: Reflections on an Afri-
can Political Paradox in Greenberg et al, supra note 171, 65 at 68.
188 Richard Albert, Constitutional Handcuffs (2010) 42:3 Ariz St LJ 663 at 678.
189 Ibid at 685.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 265
ment, which aims to freeze a distinctly historical conception of the
state,190 or we may alternatively rely on the theory of living constitution-
alism to construe the entrenched value as being consistent with trans-
formative entrenchment, which reflects more of an aspiration than a con-
cretized reality and a forward-looking project that is open to evolving
social and political norms.191
The interpretation of constitutional values is therefore not necessarily
time-bound: it may be a time-specific inquiry that compels the interpreter
to take the perspective of the authoring generation, but it may also be free
of temporal constraints. The inquiry may create what Gadamer describes
as a hermeneutical circle, which entails an interpretation that is neither
subjective nor objective, but describes understanding as the interplay of
the movement of tradition and the movement of the interpreter.192 This
interpretation proceeds from the communality that binds us to the tradi-
tion, tradition being not simply a precondition into which we come, but
we produce it ourselves, inasmuch as we understand, participate in the
evolution of tradition and hence further determine it ourselves.193 As I
suggest below, the German Constitutional Courts interpretation of the
formal amendment rules in the Basic Law exhibits elements of both his-
toricism and hermeneutics, of originalism and living constitutionalism. It
is thus a feature, not a limitation, of my account of the expressive function
of formal amendment rules that there are continuities between the con-
testability of constitutional interpretation in general and of the values en-
trenched in formal amendment rules more specifically.
The modern constitutional experience in Germany shows how political
culture aligns with the values entrenched in formal amendment rules.
The Basic Laws formal amendment rules entrench and express the con-
stitutional value of human dignity: the text states in the first section of
Article 1 that the dignity of man shall be inviolable, and adds that [t]o
respect and protect it shall be the duty of all state authority.194 The rest
of the article stresses the importance of human dignity: The German
people therefore acknowledges inviolable and inalienable human rights as
the basis of every community, of peace and of justice in the world,195 and
[t]he following basic rights shall be binding as directly valid law on legis-
190 Ibid at 678.
191 Ibid at 685.
192 Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, ed and translated by Garrett Barden & John
Cumming (New York: Crossroad, 1988) at 261.
193 Ibid.
194 Basic Law, supra note 14, art 1(1).
195 Ibid, art 1(2).
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
266
lation, administration and judiciary.196 Article 1 is entrenched as a sub-
ject-matter restriction on formal amendment, meaning that it is expressly
shielded from the Basic Laws formal amendment procedures: An
amendment to this Basic Law by which the organization of the Federation
into Laender, the basic co-operation of the Laender in legislation or the
basic principles laid down in Articles 1 and 20 are affected, shall be inad-
missible.197
In contrast to the inauthentic political commitments entrenched and
expressed only for show in sham constitutions, the Basic Laws commit-
ment to human dignity is authentic. This authenticity derives from two
principal sources: the Basic Laws design and its interpretation. First, as I
discuss below, the Basic Laws drafters intended to make human dignity
its primary constitutional value. The entrenchment of human dignity as a
subject-matter restriction was meant to be an actual constraint on gov-
ernmental conduct and was designed to convey its importance both inter-
nally to the persons bound by the Basic Law and externally to the wider
world. Second, as I also describe below, the Federal Constitutional Court
has interpreted Article 1s human dignity provision as reflecting the Basic
Laws most important constitutional value.
The Basic Law can be understood only in its historical context. As
Christian Walter has observed, [e]ach constitutional document reflects
the preoccupations of the time of its adoption.198 The Basic Law is no dif-
ferent. Under the leadership of Konrad Adenauer, the Parliamentary
Council made it a point to pass the Basic Law on May 8, 1949, both to
mark the collapse of the Third Reich four years earlier on May 8, 1945,
and to signal the beginning of a new constitutional regime.199 Adenauers
statement at the signing and proclamation of the Basic Law echoes this
theme of a new beginning: Today a new chapter is being opened in the
ever-changing history of the German people. … Those who have witnessed
the years since 1933 and the total breakdown in 1945 … are with some
emotion conscious of the fact that today … a new Germany is being creat-
ed.200 The Basic Law showed how different Germany might become.
196 Ibid, art 1(3).
197 Ibid, art 79(3).
198 Christian Walter, Human Dignity in German Constitutional Law in European Com-
mission for Democracy Through Law, The Principle of Respect for Human Dignity
(1998), online:
199 Ernst Benda, The Protection of Human Dignity (Article 1 of the Basic Law) (2000)
53:2 SMU L Rev 443 at 445.
200 Document 7: The Signing and Proclamation of the Basic Law (Grundgesetz), 23 May
1949 in Carl-Christoph Schweitzer et al, eds Politics and Government in Germany,
19441994: Basic Documents (Providence: Berghahn Books, 1995) 17 at 17.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 267
Rights protections formed the core of the new constitutional regime.
The Basic Law, writes Werner Heun, was intended to avoid a repetition
of these experiences especially by emphasizing fundamental rights and
assigning extended powers to a Constitutional Court.201 The Parliamen-
tary Council inserted the unamendable provisions into the Basic Law to
help guard against the failures of the Weimar constitution, which had
failed to curb abuses of power and constrain government conduct.202 As
Gregory Fox and Georg Nolte have written, the Basic Laws framers
reasoned that if such a clause had been present in the Weimar con-
stitution, Hitler would have been forced to violate the constitution
openly before assuming virtually dictatorial power. They concluded
that given the traditional orderly and legalistic sentiment of the
German people, this might have made a difference.203
The Basic Law thus became the first German constitution to entrench
rights for citizens and also to require the state to defend those rights
against violation.204 It is founded on rights and rooted in the experience
and in the memory of the holocaust, the war, and the liberation from un-
precedented dictatorship, ending inhumanity and tyranny by the notion of
freedom and self-determination.205 The Parliamentary Council was clear:
fundamental rights would be central, not peripheral, to the Basic Law,
and human dignity would permeate all fundamental rights.206
201 Werner Heun, The Constitution of Germany: A Contextual Analysis (Portland: Hart
Publishing, 2011) at 23.
202 Hannes Rsler, Harmonizing the German Civil Code of the Nineteenth Century with a
Modern ConstitutionThe Lth Revolution 50 Years Ago in Comparative Perspective
(2008) 23 Tul Eur & Civ L 1 ([t]he Germans realized that the rise to power of the Nazis
could be blamed to a certain degreeamong many destabilizing social, political, and
economic reasonson the construction of the Weimar Constitution of August 11, 1919
at 4 [footnotes omitted]). Though the Parliamentary Council may have attributed part
of the blame to the Weimar Constitution, the structure of Weimar Constitution was not
unsound. See Giovanni Sartori, Comparative Constitutional Engineering: An Inquiry
into Structures, Incentives and Outcomes (New York: New York University Press, 1994)
at 129. The rise of National Socialism was something that perhaps no constitutional
structure could have withstood. See Rosemary HT OKane, Paths to Democracy: Revolu-
tion and Totalitarianism (London: Routledge, 2004) at 89112, 13149.
203 Gregory H Fox & Georg Nolte, Intolerant Democracies (1995) 36:1 Harv Intl LJ 1 at
19 ×..
204 See Dennis L Bark & David R Gress, A History of West Germany: From Shadow to Sub-
stance 19451963 (Cambridge: Basil Blackwell, 1989) at 225.
205 Helmut Goerlich, Fundamental Constitutional Rights: Content, Meaning and General
Doctrines in Ulrich Karpen, ed, The Constitution of the Federal Republic of Germany:
Essays on the Basic Rights and Principles of the Basic Law with a Translation of the
Basic Law (Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, 1988) 45 at 46.
206 See Christian Starck, Constitutional Definition and Protection of Rights and Free-
doms in Christian Stark, ed, Rights, Institutions and Impact of International Law Ac-
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
268
The origin of the Basic Laws absolute entrenchment of human dignity
therefore lies in the intent to break from Germanys recent past.207 The
framers of the Basic Law entrenched human dignity as unalterable and
thereby identified it as the most fundamental constitutional rights protec-
tion in response to Germanys prior regime, under which human dignity
had been utterly trampled by the Nazis.208 The Nazi regime had empha-
sized the primacy of the state, subordinated the individual, and attributed
no intrinsic worth to the individual outside of her interaction with the
state or other individuals. The state did not exist for the citizens sake,209
according to Craig Smith and Thomas Fetzer; to the contrary, the citi-
zens existed for the sake of the state. This exaltation of the people collec-
tively, in the form of the state, combined with the denial of individual
worth to justify Nazi tyranny ideologically.210 But the Basic Laws en-
trenchment of human dignity signaled an unequivocal break with Nazi
ideology by strongly countering the core Nazi presumption of the individ-
uals lack of independent worth.211 Making human dignity unamendable
conveyed the message that the individual is unequivocally superior to the
state; the Federal Republic exists for the sake of its citizens rather than
vice versa.212 Absolute entrenchment expressed a special commitment to
respecting individual worth.213
cording to the German Basic Law: The Contributions of the Federal Republic of Germa-
ny to the Second World Congress of the International Association of Constitutional Law
(Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, 1987) 19 at 22.
207 Yet there is an uncomfortable irony in the origin of the Basic Laws absolute entrench-
ment of human dignity: its intellectual inspiration came from German constitutional
theorist and Nazi Party member, Carl Schmitt. See Ulrich K Preuss, The Implications
of Eternity Clauses: The German Experience (2011) 44:3 Isr L Rev 429 at 439. For
Schmitts explanation and defense of this exception to the rule of majoritarian democra-
cy, see Carl Schmitt, Legality and Legitimacy, ed and translated by Jeffrey Seitzer
(Durham: Duke University Press, 2004) at 3948.
208 David P Currie, The Constitution of the Federal Republic of Germany (Chicago: Univer-
sity of Chicago Press, 1994) at 11.
209 Craig T Smith & Thomas Fetzer, The Uncertain Limits of the European Court of Jus-
tices Authority: Economic Freedom Versus Human Dignity (2004) 10:3 Colum J Eur L
445 at 449.
210 Ibid.
211 Ibid at 450.
212 Ibid.
213 On this point, it is important to note the difference in entrenchment between the Basic
Law and the Draft Basic Law from 1948. The Draft Basic Law not absolutely entrench
human dignity. Article 1(1) stated that the dignity of man is under the protection of the
state, but there was no corresponding immunization of this clause from formal
amendment. The closest parallel appears in Article 20(b): As far as a fundamental
right may be restricted in accordance with the provisions of this Basic Law, its sub-
stance may not be touched. This may be interpreted as a special protection for funda-
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 269
The absolute entrenchment of human dignity has consequently creat-
ed absolute boundaries to circumscribe state power. Human dignity today
stands at the top of Germanys constitutional hierarchy. As Donald Kom-
mers explains, human dignity is the highest value of the Basic Law, the
ultimate basis of the constitutional order, and the foundation of guaran-
teed rights.214 It is, in the words of Edward Eberle, the architectonic
principle of the German legal system.215 In the leading English study of
the Basic Law, Kommers and Russell Miller write that the Basic Law
has placed human dignity at the core of its value system,216 and note
that the Basic Laws human dignity clause expresses the highest value of
the Basic Law, informing the substance and spirit of the entire docu-
ment.217 The Basic Law has expressed the states commitment to human
dignity as its most important value both through the symbolism of its en-
trenchment and likewise by the effect of its entrenchment,218 which is en-
forced by courts endowed by the Basic Law with the power to review gov-
ernmental conduct.219
C. Interpreting Constitutional Values
The consequence of entrenching human dignity absolutely against
amendment was predictable: entrenchment granted the judiciary the
power to interpret the meaning of this value. As Melissa Schwartzberg
mental rights but it is not as strong as what appears in the adopted Basic Law. The
Draft Basic Law did, however, include special formal amendment rules for federalism.
The basic formal amendment formula required two-thirds approval from both the Bun-
destag and the Bundesrat in Article 106(2). This was supplemented in Article 106(3) by
a rule that permitted a one-quarter of the Bundestag and one-quarter of the Bundesrat
to demand the amendment be ratified in a referendum by two-thirds of all voters and
by a majority of voters in a majority of the Lnder. The federalism exception appeared
in Article 107: A law by which the federal structure is essentially changed requires, in
addition to the requirements of Article 106, a three-quarters majority in the Bundes-
rat. See Civil Administration Division, Office of Military Government for Germany
(US), Draft Basic Law: Passed in First Reading in Nov/Dec 1948, (15 January 1949) at
6, 25, 9091.
214 Donald P Kommers, German Constitutionalism: A Prolegomenon (1991) 40:3 Emory
LJ 837 at 855.
215 Edward J Eberle, The German Idea of Freedom (2008) 10:1 Or Rev Intl L 1 at 5.
216 Donald P Kommers & Russell A Miller, The Constitutional Jurisprudence of the Federal
Republic of Germany, 3d ed (Durham: Duke University Press, 2012) at 44.
217 Ibid at 355.
218 See Georg Ress, The Constitution and the Requirements of Democracy in Germany in
Christian Starck, ed, New Challenges to the German Basic Law: The German Contribu-
tions to the Third World Congress of the International Association of Constitutional Law
(Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, 1991) 111 at 11718.
219 See Basic Law, supra note 14, art 19(4).
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
270
has argued, when constitutional provisions are made unamendable and
constitutional courts have final authority over the interpretation of such
provisions, entrenchment does not actually inhibit alterations,220 but ra-
ther shifts the locus of changeand the power to determine the legiti-
mate scope of mutabilityaway from legislatures and toward the
court.221 The German Constitutional Court has used this power to inter-
pret the human dignity provision as the Basic Laws supreme value,222
calling it the highest constitutional principle in the Basic Law.223 Insofar
as this interpretation conforms to the constitutional design of the Basic
Law, it is unproblematic for the Court to make such pronouncements.
Nonetheless, scholars and even judges themselves acknowledge the vast
discretionary power that the absolute entrenchment of an open-textured
provision like human dignity has conferred upon the Constitutional
Court.224
Theoretically, its absolute entrenchment exempts human dignity from
the balancing to which other rights are subject when they clash with com-
peting rights. But in practice, the Constitutional Court has interpreted
human dignity as permitting government action that justifiably violates
this value and as prohibiting governmental action that unjustifiably vio-
lates it.225 The distinction therefore turns on the extent to which the Court
is persuaded to accept the justification. The Constitutional Court has gen-
erally read the human dignity protection alongside the Basic Laws pro-
220 Melissa Schwartzberg, Democracy and Legal Change (Cambridge: Cambridge Universi-
ty Press, 2007) at 184.
221 Ibid.
222 Giovanni Bognetti, The Concept of Human Dignity in European and US Constitution-
alism in Georg Nolte, ed, European and US Constitutionalism (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2005) 85 at 93.
223 Eppler Case (1980), 54 BVerfGE 148, in Kommers & Miller, supra note 216 at 40607.
224 See e.g. Donald P Kommers, The Constitutional Law of Abortion in Germany: Should
Americans Pay Attention? (1994) 10 J Contemp Health L & Poly 1 ([t]he German
Court has also declared that these objective values arrange themselves in a hierarchy.
This can only mean that the Court itself does the arranging at 9); Kommers & Miller,
supra note 216 ([j]ustice Wolfgang Zeidler, a former president of the Federal Constitu-
tional Court, [states] …Whoever controls the [meaning of the] order of values, … controls
the constitution at 373 [footnotes omitted]). See Marc Chase McAllister, Human Dig-
nity and Individual Liberty in Germany and the United States as Examined Through
Each Countrys Leading Abortion Cases (2004) 11:2 Tulsa J Comp & Intl L
491 ([w]ith strong powers of judicial review, the Supreme Court of the United States
and Germanys Federal Constitutional Court have a great deal of control over the
meaning of their respective constitutions, and individual liberty in America and human
dignity in Germany are their primary interpretative tools at 492 [footnotes omitted])
225 See Christoph Mllers, Democracy and Human Dignity: Limits of Moralized Concep-
tion of Rights in German Constitutional Law (2009) 42:2 Isr LR 416 at 42324.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 271
tections for liberty and equality, enshrined in Articles 2226 and 3,227 respec-
tively.228 As Kommers and Miller write, the relationships among Articles
1, 2, and 3 are symbiotic.229 They continue:
Their provisions nourish and reinforce once another [and] the hu-
man dignity, liberty, and equality clauses inform the meaning of
other constitutional values just as these other values infuse the
meaning and limit the reach of the rights guaranteed by these three
fundamental articles.230
Several Constitutional Court cases exhibit the significance of human dig-
nity in German constitutional law.
In the early Microcensus Case, the Constitutional Court was asked to
rule whether the compulsory disclosure of private vacations and recrea-
tional trips in a federal census violated the Basic Laws human dignity
protection.231 The Court concluded that they did not.232 Balancing the pri-
vacy of the individual under Article 2 with the states responsibility to
govern responsibly, the Court recognized that the pressure of general pub-
lic compliance could conceivably inhibit an individuals private personal
sphere.233 But the balance here favoured the states census inquiries, both
because the inquiries preserved the respondents anonymity and did not
compel persons to disclose intimate personal details, and because individ-
226 Basic Law, supra note 14, art 2:
(1) Everyone shall have the right to free development of his personality, in-
sofar as he does not infringe the rights of others or offend against the
constitutional order or the moral code.
(2) Everyone shall have the right to life and physical inviolability. The free-
dom of the individual shall be inviolable. These rights may be interfered
with only on the basis of a law.
227 Ibid, art 3:
(1) All men shall be equal before the law.
(2) Men and women shall have equal rights.
(3) No one may be prejudiced or privileged because of his sex, descent, race,
language, homeland and origin, faith or his religious and political opin-
ions.
228 Kommers & Miller, supra note 216 at 355.
229 Ibid.
230 Ibid.
231 Ibid at 356 (translating the Microcensus Case (1969), 27 BVerfGE 1).
232 Ibid at 357.
233 Ibid.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
272
uals have a social responsibility to respond to such inquiries, which are
necessary for government planning and operations.234
In the course of upholding the governments census inquiries, the
Court discussed the human dignity provision. The Court asserted that
[h]uman dignity is at the very top of the value order of the Basic Law.235
Human dignity means that every human being is entitled to social
recognition and respect in the community;236 the state must treat persons
as something more than mere objects.237 An individual cannot be re-
quired to record and register all aspects of his or her personality, even
though such an effort is carried out anonymously in the form of a statisti-
cal survey; [the state] may not treat a person as an object subject to an in-
ventory of any kind.238 Within an individuals private personal sphere,
she is her own master.239
The Lifetime Imprisonment Case is another prominent human dignity
case in which a drug dealer killed an addict who had threatened to expose
the dealers criminal acts.240 The trial court ruled that the German Penal
Code, which set out a mandatory penalty of life imprisonment for killing
another to conceal criminal activity, ran counter to Article 1s human dig-
nity protection.241 This court held that punishing a person with a life sen-
tence with no possibility of returning to society would amount to treating
that person as mere object, and would therefore violate the states respon-
sibility to respect every persons human dignitya responsibility that ex-
tends even to a criminal.242 The Constitutional Court was then asked to
review the trial courts judgment.
234 Ibid at 35657.
235 Ibid at 356.
236 Ibid.
237 Ibid. The Constitutional Court is very serious about not treating persons as objects. In a
later case implicating the human dignity protection, the Court ruled unconstitutional
the use of a polygraph in a criminal matter. As Kommers and Miller write, [t]o elicit
the truth by attaching persons to a machine, said the Court, is to regard them as objects
and not as human begins capable of telling the truth through ordinary questioning
(ibid at 363).
238 Ibid at 356.
239 Ibid.
240 Ibid at 363 (translating the Life Imprisonment Case (1977), 45 BVerfGE 187).
241 Ibid. Capital punishment was not an option; it is prohibited in the Basic Law (supra
note 14, art 102).
242 Kommers & Miller, supra note 216 at 363.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 273
The Court ruled that life imprisonment violates human dignity where
the evidence suggests that a prisoner can be rehabilitated.243 The Court
began with Article 2(2) of the Basic Law, which authorizes Parliament to
limit an individuals right to personal freedom.244 The Court wrote, how-
ever, that this parliamentary power is itself limited, most notably by the
inviolability of human dignity, which the Court again called the highest
value of the constitutional order.245 The Court stressed that [t]his means
that the state must regard every individual within society with equal
worth246 and reiterated that [i]t is contrary to human dignity to make
persons the mere tools of the state.247 The Court connected the risk of
treating a person as an object with the punishment of lifetime imprison-
ment: [T]he state cannot turn the offender into an object of crime preven-
tion to the detriment of his or her constitutionally protected right to social
worth and respect because it would be intolerable for the state forcefully
to deprive [persons of their] freedom without at least providing them with
the chance to someday regain their freedom.248
The meaning of the Basic Laws human dignity provision becomes
clearer with this case. The state is not forbidden from sentencing a con-
victed criminal to life imprisonment, but if the state imposes this penalty,
it assumes the responsibility to work toward rehabilitating the prisoner
and helping him re-enter society:
Regarding those prisoners under life sentences, prisons also have
the duty to strive toward their resocialization, to preserve their abil-
ity to cope with life and to counteract the negative effects of incar-
ceration and the destructive changes in personality that accompany
imprisonment.249
This responsibility flows from the Basic Laws human dignity protection:
This task finds its justification in the constitution itself; it can be inferred
from the guarantee of the inviolability of human dignity within the mean-
ing of Article 1(1) of the Basic Law.250 The Court understood this duty to
rehabilitate as interconnected with Article 1 insofar as rehabilitation is
constitutionally required in any community that establishes human digni-
243 Ibid at 367.
244 Ibid at 364.
245 Ibid.
246 Ibid.
247 Ibid.
248 Ibid.
249 Ibid at 366.
250 Ibid.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
274
ty as its centerpiece and commits itself to the principle of social justice.251
What appears to underpin the inviolability of human dignity is the rejec-
tion of persons as objects.
Perhaps the most useful case to demonstrate the Basic Laws hierar-
chy of constitutional values is the 1975 Abortion I Case.252 The subject of
the case was section 218a of the Abortion Reform Act of 1974, which re-
moved criminal prohibitions on abortion provided that the procedure was
performed by a licensed physician on a consenting woman during the first
twelve weeks of pregnancy.253 Criminal penalties continued to apply for
other abortions procured after the third month of pregnancy, with the ex-
ception of those pregnancies resulting from rape or incest or those termi-
nated on medical advice.254 The new law also required a woman to consult
with a physician or a counseling agency about assistance available to
pregnant women, mothers, and children.255 Several members of the Ger-
man Bundestag (the national lower house) as well as a number of German
states petitioned the Constitutional Court to review whether the new law
violated Article 1s human dignity provision and Article 2s right to life
provision, among other constitutional rights.256 This compelled the Court
to weigh the competing rights of the mother and the fetus, whose develop-
ing life the Court noted is protected by Article 2(2) of the Basic Law.257
Relying on the Basic Laws ordering of values to reach is decision, the
Constitutional Court found the new abortion law incompatible with the
fetuss human dignity and right to life.258 It stated, before reaching the
merits of the case, that its deliberation demands a total view of the con-
stitutional norms and the hierarchy of values contained therein.259 Rec-
ognizing the importance of the case, the Court added that [t]he gravity
and seriousness of the constitutional questions posed become clear if it is
considered that what is involved here is the protection of human life, one
of the central values of every legal order.260 The Court stressed that its
task was not to judge the new abortion law against the values established
251 Ibid.
252 Ibid at 374 (translating the Abortion I Case (1975), 39 BverfGE 1).
253 Ibid.
254 Ibid.
255 Ibid.
256 Ibid. The Basic Laws right to life provision holds that [e]veryone shall have the right
to life and physical inviolability (Basic Law, supra note 14, art 2(2)(1)).
257 Ibid at 37677.
258 Kommers & Miller, supra note 216 at 374.
259 Ibid at 374.
260 Ibid.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 275
under another countrys constitution but rather against the values en-
trenched in the German Basic Law.261 The Court ultimately held that the
law is void insofar as it exempts termination of pregnancy from punish-
ment in cases where no reasons exist whichwithin the meaning of the
[present] decisional groundshave priority over the value order contained
in the Basic Law.262
Constitutional history played a significant part in the Courts judg-
ment. The Court explained that the Basic Laws entrenchment of the
right to life was the result of the destruction of life that Germany had
seen in its past:
[T]he categorical inclusion of the inherently self-evident right to life
in the Basic Law may be explained principally as a reaction to the
destruction of life unworthy to live, the final solution, and the liq-
uidations that the National Socialist regime carried out as govern-
mental measures.263
Under the Basic Law, the right to life affirms
the fundamental value of human life and of a state concept that is
emphatically opposed to the views of a political regime for which the
individual life had little significance and that therefore practiced un-
limited abuse in the name of the arrogated right over life and death
of the citizen.264
The Court therefore contrasted the Weimar constitution and the regime
that followed it with the Basic Law and the new regime that it sought to
create.
Noting that the Basic Law is clear in its language that everyone shall
have the right to lifewith no delimitation of the various developmental
stages of human life265the Court affirmed that the right extends to the
unborn, or what the Court called developing life.266 The Court then tied
the right to life to human dignity, explaining that the obligation to protect
the right to life follows from Article 1: Wherever human life exists, it
merits human dignity; whether the subject of this dignity is conscious of it
and knows how to safeguard it is not important. The potential capabilities
inherent in human existence from its inception are adequate to merit
human dignity.267 Yet the Court also acknowledged that the state has an
261 Ibid.
262 Ibid.
263 Ibid.
264 Ibid.
265 Ibid.
266 Ibid at 37576.
267 Ibid at 376.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
276
obligation to protect the life of the mother and that the mothers pregnan-
cy exists within her private personal sphere: The obligation of the state
to take the developing life under its protection also exists in principle with
regard to the mother. … Pregnancy belongs to the intimate sphere of the
woman that is constitutionally protected by Article 2 (1) in conjunction
with Article 1 (1) of the Basic Law.268 It is at this point that the Court in-
voked the hierarchy of constitutional values to resolve the collision be-
tween the rights of the developing life and the rights of the mother.
The Constitutional Court saw the conflict of rights as inhospitable to
any compromise: No compromise is possible that would both guarantee
the protection of the unborn life and concede to the pregnant woman the
freedom of terminating the pregnancy because termination of pregnancy
always means destruction of the prenatal life.269 In choosing which of
these two rights to privilege, the Court felt itself bound to use the human
dignity provision as its guide: In the ensuing balancing process, both
constitutional values must be perceived in their relation to human dignity
as the center of the constitutions value system.270 As a result, the Court
elevated the right of the fetus over the right of the mother. In the Courts
view, whereas prohibiting abortion only impairs a womans right to self-
determination, abortion destroys life: When using Article 1 (1) as a
guidepost, the decision must come down in favor of the preeminence of
protecting the fetuss life over the right of self-determination of the preg-
nant woman.271 Although the Court conceded that [p]regnancy, birth,
and child-rearing may impair the womans right of self-determination and
the right to many personal developmental potentialities,272 it held as de-
terminative that [t]he termination of pregnancy, however, destroys pre-
natal life.273 The difference between the impairment of human dignity
and its destruction was therefore great enough to tilt the Court toward
protecting the right of the fetus.
As a final illustration of how the Constitutional Court has interpreted
the Basic Laws inviolable human dignity provision, consider the more re-
cent Aviation Security Act Case.274 The case arose out of the Aviation Se-
curity Act, which Germany adopted in the aftermath of the terrorist at-
268 Ibid.
269 Ibid.
270 Ibid (quoting the Abortion I Case (1975), 39 BverfGE 1).
271 Ibid at 377.
272 Ibid.
273 Ibid.
274 Ibid at 396 (discussing and translating in part the Aviation Security Act Case (2006),
115 BVerfGE 118).
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 277
tacks of September 11, 2001 in the United States.275 The law authorized
the German Minister of Defence, with the consent of the Minister of the
Interior, to order the armed forces to shoot down a commercial aircraft
thought to be hijacked in order to be used as a weapon against civilian
targets.276 The Constitutional Court found the law unconstitutional on
several grounds, notably because it would deprive passengers and crew of
their right to self-determination and thus make them mere objects of the
states rescue operation for the protection of others.277
The Constitutional Courts refusal to authorize the state to treat a
planes passengers as objects recalled its earlier decisions in the Microsen-
sus Case and the Life Imprisonment Case. As Kommers and Miller ex-
plain, the Court stated that killing may not be employed as a means to
save others, for human lives may not be disposed of unilaterally by the
state in this way, even on the basis of a statutory authorization.278 The
Court ultimately held that an aircraft may not be shot downand there
is no constitutional state duty to shoot it downsimply because it may be
used as a weapon to extinguish life on the ground, particularly since the
ensuing loss of life would not bring an end to the body politic or the consti-
tutional system.279 The Court again referred to the pre-eminence of hu-
man dignity as a constitutional value: Human life is intrinsically con-
nected to human dignity as a paramount principle of the constitution and
the highest constitutional value.280
These four leading cases on Germanys inviolable human dignity pro-
vision illustrate the authenticity of the political commitments entrenched
in the Basic Laws formal amendment rules, insofar as the entrenched
value aligns with its interpretation and enforcement by political actors.
Yet the constitutional design of the Basic Law and its interpretation by
the Constitutional Court cannot, on their own, fully explain the alignment
between German political culture and the entrenched constitutional value
of human dignity. The Basic Laws design and its interpretation have cer-
tainly contributed to the process of sowing and growing the constitu-
tional value of human dignity;281 yet the legislatures deference to the
275 Ibid.
276 Ibid.
277 Ibid (quoting the Aviation Security Act Case (2006), 115 BVerfGE 118, 154).
278 Ibid at 397.
279 Ibid.
280 Ibid.
281 Eckart Klein, Human Dignity in German Law in David Kretzmer & Eckart Klein,
eds, The Concept of Human Dignity in Human Rights Discourse (The Hague: Kluwer
Law International, 2002) 145 at 159.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
278
Court has also helped, particularly where the Court has invalidated legis-
lation on the basis of the human dignity provision and the legislature has
responded by re-passing the law into conformity with the Courts recom-
mendations.282 Germans themselves have also accepted as worthy and le-
gitimate the absolute entrenchment of human dignity, as I discuss below.
The German Basic Law recently marked its sixtieth anniversary. On
that occasion, German constitutional theorist Matthias Mahlmann offered
his reflections, calling the Basic Law a resilient constitution and a re-
markable success and noting proudly that [s]ome aspects of the Basic
Law have even become a kind of attractive export article not accounted
for in Germanys foreign trade balance, but nevertheless of considerable
importance.283 Mahlmanns analysis underscored the importance of the
Basic Laws human dignity protection, which, in his view, has come to de-
fine the Basic Law in the public perception:
The norm, however, that most characterizes the Basic Law in the
public perception and in scholarly reflection is the guarantee of hu-
man dignity. This particular role is, to a large degree, a consequence
of the German past. Nazism still legitimizes the guarantee of human
dignity today by the abominable, vivid barbarism of its negation.
The guarantee of human dignity formulates, however, not only the
desire to refrain from fathoming yet another time a moral abyss, but
a promise as well: the perspective to create a legal order that embod-
ies principles of human dignity not only through the absence of mis-
deeds, but also through legally institutionalized structures of a re-
publican culture of respect.284
The concept of human dignity has risen in public esteem as it has been
applied across more spheres of German life. George Fletcher states the
point: When the German Basic Law of 1949 declares human dignity to be
the foundational value of the constitution, the implications run through
all relationships that may come into being.285 Not only does human digni-
ty prescribe or proscribe state action, it also influences private action. The
Constitutional Court has emphasized this point when explaining that the
Basic Law entrenches an objective order of values.286 For the Court, the
282 One of the most prominent examples is the 1976 Abortion Reform Act, passed in the af-
termath of the Abortion I Case. See Kommers & Miller, supra note 216 at 38485.
283 Matthias Mahlmann, The Basic Law at 60Human Dignity and the Culture of Re-
publicanism (2010) 11:1 German Law Journal 9 at 9.
284 Ibid at 10 [footnotes omitted].
285 George P Fletcher, Our Secret Constitution: How Lincoln Redefined American Democra-
cy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001) at 216.
286 Kommers & Miller, supra note 216 at 444 (translating the Lth Case (1958), 7 BverfGE
198).
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 279
Basic Law is not a value-neutral document.287 It is a value-laden text
whose purpose is to protect rights in all spheres: This value system,
which centers upon dignity of the human personality developing freely
within the social community, must be looked upon as a fundamental con-
stitutional decision affecting all spheres of law, both public and private.288
The Basic Laws constitutional hierarchy thus creates a value system ex-
tending beyond the public sphere: Every provision of private law must be
compatible with this system of values, and every such provision must be
interpreted in its spirit, declared the Court in the pivotal 1958 Luth
Case.289
The application of the Basic Laws constitutional provisions to the pri-
vate sphere has been called the third party effect doctrine.290 Under this
doctrine, the Constitutional Court interprets and applies the values of the
Basic Law in such a way that vindicates those values, whether the matter
is constitutional or civil.291 Frank Michelman calls this the double aspect
of the Basic Laws rights protections:
As specifically worded guarantees (subjective rights), they obligate
only the state and its officials. These clauses also, however, speak
as a fundamental constitutional decision of the German peoplefor
a set of underlying values and principles, an objective value system
for the whole of German civic life.292
Michelman adds that the Basic Laws value-orderings must, accordingly,
influence the civil law throughout, obligating ordinary judges to construe
and apply the background-law provisions of the Civil Code always in its
spirit and never in contradiction with it.293 This language tracks the
Courts own; the Court has stated that [t]his system infuses specific con-
stitutional content into private law, which from that point on determines
287 Ibid.
288 Ibid.
289 Ibid.
290 See e.g. Edward J Eberle, Equality in Germany and the United States (2008) 10:1 San
Diego Intl LJ 63 at 97; Stephen Gardbaum, The Myth and the Reality of American
Constitutional Exceptionalism (2008) 107:3 Mich L Rev 391 at 433; Christian Starck,
Human Rights and Private Law in German Constitutional Development and in the
Jurisdiction of the Federal Constitutional Court in Daniel Friedmann & Daphne Bar-
ak-Erez, ed, Human Rights in Private Law (Portland: Hart Publishing, 2001) 97 at 97.
291 See Edward J Eberle, Public Discourse in Contemporary Germany (1997) 47:3 Case
W Res L Rev 797 at 81316.
292 Frank I Michelman, The Interplay of Constitutional and Ordinary Jurisdiction in
Ginsburg & Dixon, supra note 25, 278 at 289.
293 Ibid.
(2013) 59:2 MCGILL LAW JOURNAL REVUE DE DROIT DE MCGILL
280
its interpretation.294 It is important to note, however, that this doctrine
does not contemplate the application of the Basic Laws rights protections
directly to private individuals, but only indirectly, through the Basic
Laws application to private law.295
The constitutional value of human dignity therefore derives its force
from its entrenchment in the Basic Law, its interpretation by the Consti-
tutional Court, and its centrality to German political culture. The late
German political theorist observed that modern Germany has become,
not only by the rules of its constitution but also in the reality of its consti-
tutional life …[,] a state which has taken seriously its obligations to create
favorable external conditions for its citizens to achieve a life in conformity
with human dignity.296 That Germanys highest constitutional value is
ordered objectively means that it is legally binding upon the entire consti-
tutional community.297 As Stphanie Hennette-Vauchez writes, [t]his ob-
jective nature is crucial to securing the success of the principle of human
dignity. In fact, such objectivity reinforces considerably its actual norma-
tive strength.298 This transformation of the Basic Laws normative aspi-
rations from subjective to objective values is critical to understanding how
the values entrenched in the Basic Laws formal amendment rules have
become and have since remained authentic political commitments.
Conclusion
Formal amendment rules do more than serve a corrective purpose.
Constitutional designers may entrench formal amendment rules not only
to serve the conventional functions scholars attribute to these rulesto
distinguish the constitution from ordinary law, to structure the formal
amendment process, to precommit political actors, to make improvements
or corrections, to heighten public awareness, to check political branches,
to promote democracy, and to pacify constitutional changebut also to
294 Kommers & Miller, supra note 216 at 444 (translating the Lth Case (1958), 7 BverfGE
198).
295 See Greg Taylor, The Horizontal Effect of Human Rights Provisions, the German Mod-
el and Its Applicability to Common-Law Jurisdictions (2002) 13:2 Kings College Law
Journal 187 at 200.
296 Kurt Sontheimer, Principles of Human Dignity in the Federal Republic in Paul
Kirchhof & Donald P Kommers, eds, Germany and its Basic Law: Past, Present, and
FutureA GermanAmerican Symposium (Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft,
1993) 213 at 216.
297 See Stphanie Hennette-Vauchez, A Human Dignitas? Remnants of the Ancient Legal
Concept in Contemporary Dignity Jurisprudence (2011) 9:1 International Journal of
Constitutional Law 32 at 44.
298 Ibid at 43.
THE EXPRESSIVE FUNCTION OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT RULES 281
express constitutional values. Constitutional designers may entrench and
thereby express special political commitments in the rules that govern
how the constitutional text is formally amended, for example through the
creation of escalating or non-escalating amendment procedures or subject-
matter restrictions.
That formal amendment rules may express constitutional values is
both a clarifying and a complicating contribution to the study of such
rules. It is clarifying insofar as it illuminates a function of the rules that
scholars have yet to fully explain and illustrate, but it is complicating
since we cannot know from text alone whether the values entrenched in
formal amendment rules reflect authentic or inauthentic political com-
mitments. We must therefore take a skeptical posture to any special or
absolute entrenchment of constitutional values and inquire whether these
formally entrenched values align in reality with a states political culture.
We have seen with respect to the values entrenched in the Basic Laws
formal amendment rules, for example, that German constitutional en-
trenchment aligns strongly with Germanys political culture. This align-
ment appears attributable largely to the Basic Laws constitutional design
and its interpretation, as well as to the popular legitimacy of the Basic
Laws absolute entrenchment of human dignity.
There remains much to study about the expressive function of formal
amendment rules. The field of comparative constitutional law could bene-
fit from jurisdiction-specific case studies on the concordance between the
values entrenched and expressed in formal amendment rules and those
recognized by political actors and citizens. There are also important ques-
tions about the strategic, historical, and local reasons why constitutional
designers choose to entrench certain constitutional values instead of oth-
ers. It may additionally be useful to inquire into the degree to which the
values entrenched in formal amendment rules are actually vindicated in
the judgments of national courts of last resort, to the extent that those
values are even justiciable. These and other inquiries into the study of
formal amendment rules hold promise for enriching the study of compara-
tive constitutional law and constitutional design.